Abstract
Inspired by the one-hundredth anniversary of the seminal works of Stern and Gerlach, our contribution is a proposal of how to use their famous experiment in a more contemporary perspective. Our main idea is to re-cast the experiment in the modern language of prepare-and-measure scenarios. By doing so, it is possible to connect geometric and algebraic aspects of the space of states with the physical space. We also discuss possible simulations of the SG experiment as well as some experimental properties of the experiment revealed at the statistical level. Merging a more modern perspective with a paradigmatic experiment, we hope this paper can serve as an entry door for quantum information theory and the.
Keywords:
Stern-Gerlach experiment; Qubits; Bloch sphere; Dimension witnesses
1. Introduction
The Stern-Gerlach (SG) experiment branches over all corners of quantum theory. It extends from the very beginning historical aspects of quantum mechanics, concerning the spatial quantization of the angular momentum angle of an atom in relation to a proper magnetic field within the Sommerfeld atomic model [1[1] O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 7, 253 (1921).] and its follow-up, showing positive results on this the subject [2[2] W. Gerlach and O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 8, 111 (1921).]. The most remembered papers were published a bit later, in 1922 [3[3] W. Gerlach and O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 9, 349 (1922)., 4[4] W. Gerlach and O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 9, 353 (1922).]. They are closely attached to the spin discovery, although it was not clear at that time [5[5] G.G. Gomes and M. Pietrocola, Revista Brasileira de Ensino de Física 33, 2604 (2011).]. Currently, it is the basis for state-of-art measurements on qubits [6[6] T.-Y. Wu, A. Kumar, F. Giraldo and D. S. Weiss, Nature Physics 15, 538 (2019).].
Essentially, the experiment consists of sending a beam of particles through an inhomogeneous magnetic field. Simply put, classical descriptions predict some sort of continuous Gaussian-spread profile for the outcomes of this experiment. Contrary to the classical prediction, the beam is not located in one single spot: it is split into two [7[7] C. Cohen-Tannoudji, B. Diu and F. Laloë, Quantum mechanics. Basic concepts, tools, and applications (Wiley-VCH, Weinheim, 2020), v.1, 2 ed.].
Even though the SG experiment has been deeply discussed in Ref. [8[8] J.J. Sakurai and J. Napolitano, Modern quantum mechanics (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017), 2 ed.], in this contribution, however, we would like to use it as a complete tool kit to analyze its very quantum nature, putting aside technical or experimental details. We propose a couple of further investigations. Namely,
-
A concatenation of two SG experiments is a physical proxy for what is called a “prepare-and-measure” scenario [10[10] C. de Gois, G. Moreno, R. Nery, S. Brito, R. Chaves and R. Rabelo, PRX Quantum 2, 030311 (2021)., 11[11] M.A. Nielsen and I.L. Chuang, Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011), 10 ed.].
-
The space of states in an SG setup is two-dimensional; whose generic element is usually called a qubit over the field of complex numbers). Other examples, such as photon polarization or even the double slit experiment, are on equal footing. For this case, it is customary to write an arbitrary vector using the standard state parametrization [11[11] M.A. Nielsen and I.L. Chuang, Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011), 10 ed.]
with and . In this case, the vector states lie in what is called a Bloch sphere. Our manuscript provides an operational meaning for the parameters and . Rather than a mere mathematical parametrization, the pair identifies the orientation of the magnet used in the preparation of states on the three-dimensional physical space, giving rise to (1). This intrinsic connection between the three-dimensional (real) space and the two-dimensional (complex) space of states is explored through the Hopf fibration. We discuss it in detail in Appendix A.
-
Finally, and not less important, we address the current problem of dimension witnesses [12[12] N. Brunner, M. Navascués and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. Lett. 110, 150501 (2013)., 13[13] N. Brunner, D. Cavalcanti, S. Pironio, V. Scarani and S. Wehner, Reviews of Modern Physics 86, 419 (2014).]. The main goal of this research area consists of determining how many degrees of freedom an unknown physical system has only looked at the measured data. For the particular representation of quantum systems with Hilbert spaces, it means to find its dimension given a set of some conditional probabilities or quantum correlations. We will show that, for the canonical case of an SG setup, the dimension d = 2 is recovered when one tights a particular quantum witness.
In light of the historical and technical comments above, we put this manuscript forward not only to celebrate one hundred years of the seminal SG works but also to explore its pedagogical potential. Recently, the pedagogical approach to quantum mechanics has been found to be conducted through two main lines: one can focus on spin first [14[14] C. Manogue, AIP Conference Proceedings 1413, 55 (2012).], or one can give more emphasis on wave function first [15[15] N.L. Harshman, American Journal of Physics 87, 237 (2019).]. Our work is based on the former. By focusing on spin first, fundamental aspects of quantum theory turn out to be more transparent. For instance, in the SG case, superposition is one of these key aspects that transparently stand out. As we will discuss in more detail below, it is possible to re-frame the SG experiment in a more modern scenario. By emphasizing in a device-independent manner the preparation and the measurements, this re-framing abstracts away the experimental complexities surrounding the original SG device. Focusing exclusively on toy models for preparations and measurements gives the natural framework to design protocols of quantum communication and quantum cryptography — both on the research level and on the pedagogical level. For instance, one can easily understand quantum teleporting [16[16] C.H. Bennett, G. Brassard, C. Crépeau, R. Jozsa, A. Peres and W.K. Wootters, Physical Review Letters 70, 1895 (1993).] or even more paradigmatic algorithms of quantum cryptography (like the famous BB84 [17[17] C.H. Bennett and G. Brassard, Proceedings of IEEE International Conference on Computers, Systems and Signal Processing 175, 8 (1984)]) under this prepare-and-measure scenario.
The paper is divided as follows. Section 2 2. Simulating a Prepare-and-measure Scenario The so-called prepare-and-measure scenario basically consists of two boxes [9, 10, 18]. The first one has Nx buttons that prepare the system in a state ρx under demand. The second box has other Ny buttons that perform measurements, providing different outcomes labelled by a=1,…,k. Fig. 1 depicts this idea. Figure 1: Schematic representation of a prepare-and-measure scenario, with an outcome a=2. When no more information about the nature of the physical systems involved in this scenario is available to the experimentalist, the only thing they can do is describe it through a set of conditional probabilities Pr(a|x,y) of getting an outcome a, after preparing the system with x and measuring y. Note that this is exactly what a sequence of two SG devices provides. In fact, to push a button x means, operationally, to select a direction to the magnetic field that separates the flux of particles in two, together with blocking one of the resultant split beams, while the other is free to move on (into the measurement device). Care must be taken when we say “the direction” of the magnetic field in this case. One possible realization of the inhomogeneous magnetic field of the SG device is given by (2) B → ( r → ) = - ξ x e ^ 1 + ( B 0 + ξ z ) e ^ 3 where {e^i,i=1,2,3} is the basis of the physical space of displacement vectors ⅅ (≅ℝ3), with coordinates x, y and z [19]. B0 is the component of B→ in the z direction. ξ represents small deviations in the sense that |ξz| and |ξx| are much smaller than |B0|. It guarantees that (i) we have an inhomogeneous magnetic field and (ii) ∇⋅B→=0, as expected. In this case, we say that the magnetic field points towards the z direction, by an abuse of notation. We may also realize what the y-button represents. It defines another direction of a magnetic field, that, once again, may split the income beam into two. In one of the exits, there is a wall to stop the outcome beam. On the other, though, there is a Geiger-count type detector. This is the spirit of what once was called a “Yes-No” experiment or proposition – the core of older quantum systems descriptions based on the propositional calculus [20]. In modern terminology, we call it a projective measurement (on a qubit) or a test [21]. It is specified by a set ℳ={|ψ-⟩,|ψ+⟩}. If we measure the qubit prepared in the state ρx, then the possible outcomes are - or +, interpreted here as being blocked by the wall or counted by the detector. This structure may also be rephrased, noting that y can be interpreted not only as a measurement but also as a preparation of states. Hence, the measurement of the second box can be restated by the (yes-no) question: once the system is prepared in the state ρx, is the system in the state ρy? Questions of the form: “What is the state of the system?” seems to be difficult to be approached experimentally [22, 23, 24]. is dedicated to introducing the prepare-and-measure scenario, modulated by a concatenation of two SG devices. In Section 3 3. Experimental Facts Concerning the SG Experiment The basic experimental fact concerning the sequence of two SG devices in the prepare-and-measure scenario is related to a conditional probability. We will use the following notation. Each x (or y) button of preparation (or measure) is defined by a direction r^x (r^y) in the physical space, that orients the magnetic field. Moreover, it also selects either one (+) or the other (-) split beam (both in x, allowing one of the scattered beams to head into the measuring device and y, to set the detector). So, we define (3) x ⟷ r ^ x + or r ^ x - . This notation is explored1 in Fig. 2. In this case, r^x+ selects the beam with spin up in the z direction. Else, r^y+ counts the atoms that fire the wall with spin up in a direction rotated by π/6 of the first magnetic field. This figure also shows a particular example of an experimental fact, (4) P r ( + | r ^ x + , r ^ y + ) = 1 + cos < ( r ^ x + , r ^ y + ) 2 . Figure 2: Experimental scheme of two SG devices generated by the PhET interactive simulation. To see this, we have plotted the graph in Fig. 3, with a repeated sequence of SG experiments, keeping r^x fixed while varying r^y. The curious result is consistent with (4). The data used to plot the graph was, once again, collected using the SG PhET interactive simulations: it is possible to define the angle between the magnetic fields in both devices. Figure 3: Pr(+|r^x+,r^y+) as a function of the angle between r^x and r^y. Before moving on to complete the construction of states in this particular experiment, let us discuss a peculiar feature of a concatenation of SG devices, which is related to the concept of reproducibility of tests. Let us set a sequence of two SG devices, fully characterized by r^+. We find that Pr(+|r^+,r^+)=1. In other words, the question of having the states prepared and measured by the same magnetic field is answered with 100% of certainty. Furthermore, we could insert another box after the two ones, asking the same question. The answer would be “yes” repeatedly. Now comes the tricky step, which has no immediate classical counterpart [25]. Let us consider three SG devices, characterized by, say, r^+, u^+ and r^+, respectively. Each box may be interpreted as either prepare or measuring device. This is so because the income beam, as previously discussed, is divided by two. The first and the third are the same. However, the second test destroys the preparation performed by the first box. Thus, the answer in the third one is not responded to repeatedly. In this sense, the first and second tests are called incompatible. Conversely, two distinct tests, say 𝒜 and ℬ are called compatible whenever the test ℬ, applied in between two repetitions of 𝒜, does not affect the reproducibility of 𝒜. We point out that this situation is drastically different from its classical counterpart. In fact, for a spinning top, with angular momentum L→=Iω→, one could obtain, say ωx and ωy simultaneously. Here, I stands for the moment of inertia, and ω→ is the corresponding angular velocity [8]. , we explore some experimental facts related to the scheme previously presented. Leveraging on geometrical grounds, we construct the Bloch sphere in Sec. 4 4. Bloch Sphere Unveiled The discussion presented so far hasn’t revealed the proper representation of states in the SG experiment. The incompatibility of tests discussed before is just a piece of evidence for its quantum description. Besides that, the division of the income beam in two indicates that we could use a two-dimensional Hilbert space to fully represent the experiment. Let us assume, then, that the state of space is just ℂ2, with vectors denoted by the standard Dirac notation. This ad hoc imposition leads to the correct conditional probability (4) through a Born rule, to be presented in a while, see (34) and (35). We will also construct the Bloch sphere here. To do so, we divide our tasks into subsections. In the first one, we try to explore a liaison between the geometry of Hilbert spaces and probabilities. Then, we direct our efforts to the Bloch sphere itself. Finally, a list of comments will be given. 4.1. Geometry of probabilities The parametrization given in (1) reflects a clean geometrical meaning in terms of the preparation of states. In fact, the pair (θ,φ) uniquely describes the state prepared by (5) x ⟷ r ^ x + = sin θ cos φ e ^ 1 + sin θ sin φ e ^ 2 + cos θ e ^ 3 , that is, the radial arbitrary direction in spherical coordinates in the physical space that indicates the magnetic field orientation. As usual, {e^i,i=1,2,3} is the canonical basis of ℝ3. Let us clarify this point. As mentioned before, the two split beams indicate that ℂ2 is a good candidate for the space of states. Let us choose a basis in ℂ2. By pressing the x-button of preparation, we select a particular direction in space to point the magnetic field as well as one of the scattered beams. So, we take (6) x 1 ⟷ e ^ 3 + ⟷ | 0 ⟩ , x 2 ⟷ e ^ 3 - ⟷ | 1 ⟩ . It means that the vectors |0⟩ and |1⟩ represent the two possible preparations. These two possible choices mean that the system may bear excluding properties (i.e., of being selected by x1 or x2 in (6)). So, we associate a property of the system to a subspace in the state of space. There is one way to describe what is the probability of a system to posses a particular property: we look at the projection of the state vector onto the corresponding subspace. This geometry of probabilities asks for a inner-product in ℂ2, ⟨|⟩:ℂ2×ℂ2→ℂ. For our case, if the system is prepared in the state |1⟩, it should have no component in the subspace spanned by |0⟩. In fact, the properties of being selected by x1 or x2 are excluded. Thus, ⟨0||1⟩=0, which also implies that 𝒵={|0⟩,|1⟩} can be taken as a basis for ℂ2, as they are linearly independent. Along with the lines above, for a general state vector (7) | ψ ⟩ = α | 0 ⟩ + β | 1 ⟩ , where |α|2 represents the probability of the system to be measured by y1⟷e^3+ as well as |β|2 by y2⟷e^3-, owing to the geometry of probabilities so constructed. Mathematically, we project |ψ⟩ on the corresponding subspace and take the square. That is, if r^+⟷|ψ⟩=α|0⟩+β|1⟩, then (8) P r ( + | r ^ + , e ^ 3 + ) = | ⟨ 0 | | ψ ⟩ | 2 = | α | 2 , P r ( - | r ^ + , e ^ 3 - ) = | ⟨ 1 | | ψ ⟩ | 2 = | β | 2 . Instead of |0⟩ and |1⟩, one could take projectors to represent states, (9) ρ x 1 = | 0 ⟩ ⟨ 0 | , ρ x 2 = | 1 ⟩ ⟨ 1 | , or even ρx=|ψ⟩⟨ψ|. The probabilities estimated in (8) assume the form (10) P r ( + | r ^ + , e ^ 3 + ) = T r ( ρ x ρ x 1 ) = | α | 2 , P r ( - | r ^ + , e ^ 3 - ) = T r ( ρ x ρ x 2 ) = | β | 2 . In this case, one or the other option will be answered. So, |α|2+|β|2=1 has a clear meaning in terms of probabilities. Another possible geometrical origin to quantum probabilities (and their difference to the classical ones) may be found in [26]. 4.2. Geometrical interpretation to the Blochsphere Our final task consists of finding the complex coefficients α and β in terms of the duple (θ,φ) that defines r^+ uniquely, see (5). Firstly, we may guess what are the states corresponding to the preparations e^1±. According to Pr(+|e^1+,e^3+)=Pr(-|e^1-,e^3-)=12, the prepared states oscillate when asked about e^3+. Thus, (11) e ^ 1 + ⟷ 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ + | 1 ⟩ ) = : | + ⟩ , e ^ 1 - ⟷ 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ - | 1 ⟩ ) = : | - ⟩ , and ⟨+|-⟩=0, as expected (the properties of being prepared by e^1+ and e^1- are excluding). The set 𝒳={|+⟩,|-⟩} could also be taken as a basis for ℂ2. The change 𝒵→𝒳 can be seen as a rotation of π/4 (or a unitary transformation in the case of complex vector spaces). Likewise, we can “rotate” in the complex state of spaces both |0⟩ and |1⟩ by a π/4 factor to generate the basis 𝒴={|a⟩,|b⟩}. First, we write (12) | a ′ ⟩ = 1 2 ( e i π 4 | 0 ⟩ + e - i π 4 | 1 ⟩ ) , | b ′ ⟩ = 1 2 ( e i π 4 | 0 ⟩ - e - i π 4 | 1 ⟩ ) . Noting that a global phase factor is irrelevant (in the sense of preserving probabilities), we finally define (13) | a ⟩ = e - i π 4 | a ′ ⟩ = 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ - i | 1 ⟩ ) , | b ⟩ = e - i π 4 | b ′ ⟩ = 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ + i | 1 ⟩ ) . As in the case of 𝒵 and 𝒳, 𝒴 is also formed by orthonormal vectors and (14) e ^ 2 ± ⟷ 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ ± i | 1 ⟩ ) . They generate the correct oscillations of 50%/50% in the probabilities, (15) P r ( ± | e ^ i + , e ^ j ± ) = 1 2 , i , j = 1,2,3 , i ≠ j . With the basis 𝒳, 𝒴 and 𝒵 we are in position to obtain the coefficients α and β in (7), such that r^+⟷|ψ⟩ and r^ is an arbitrary direction in the physical space. Invoking once again that the conditional probability (4) is only a function of the angles between the magnetic field vectors involved in preparing and measuring, we have (16) P r ( + | r ^ + , e ^ 3 + ) = 1 + r ^ ⋅ e ^ 3 2 = 1 + cos θ 2 = | α | 2 . The last equality holds due to the geometry of probabilities constructed so far. So, α=cosθ2eiλ,λ∈ℝ. Since a global phase factor does not influence probabilities, we hide eiλ in β. Following this spirit and knowing that (17) e ^ 1 + ⟷ | + ⟩ = 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ + | 1 ⟩ ) , e ^ 2 + ⟷ | a ⟩ = 1 2 ( | 0 ⟩ + i | 1 ⟩ ) , we have (18) P r ( + | r ^ + , e ^ 1 + ) = 1 + sin θ cos φ 2 = | ⟨ + | ψ ⟩ | 2 ⇒ ⇒ 1 + sin θ cos φ = cos 2 θ 2 + cos θ 2 ( β + β * ) + | β | 2 . Since |β|2=1-|α|2=1-cos2θ2, we find, (19) R e β = sin θ 2 cos φ . Analogously, (20) P r ( + | r ^ + , e ^ 2 + ) = 1 + sin θ sin φ 2 = | ⟨ a | ψ ⟩ | 2 implies (21) I m ( β ) = sin θ 2 sin φ . If we now gather all the pieces, then b=sinθ2eiφ and (22) r ^ + ⟷ | ψ ⟩ = cos θ 2 | 0 ⟩ + e i φ sin θ 2 | 1 ⟩ , completing our final objective of operationally constructing (1). To avoid a lengthy discussion here, we leave the next subsection for general comments and discussions concerning our approach. 4.3. General comments and discussions Starting from a three-dimensional physical space, we may construct a two-dimensional state of spaces. Actually, we assumed that we had a two-dimensional Hilbert space. This assumption has led us to a theoretical construction that fits perfectly with the experimental data available. What can be said about the inverse? The existence of qubits necessarily needs a three-dimensional space? Our construction has shown a geometrical significance to the pair (θ,φ) used to parametrize state vectors, given by (22). If the pair runs values in the standard domain θ∈[0,π] and φ∈[0,2π], then we cover the unit sphere, and so does |ψ⟩ over what is called the Bloch sphere. With a fixed φ=0, the two vectors with θ=0 and θ=π are connected with the following states, (23)r^1+=e^3+⟷|0⟩,r^2+=-e^3+⟷|1⟩. This calculation indicates a general result: antipodes on the unit sphere S2 are related to orthonormal states. In fact, in physical space, the pairs (θ,φ) and (π-θ,φ+π) generate a couple of antipodes and, as stated, we have (24)r^+(θ,φ)⟷|ψ+⟩=cosθ2|0⟩+eiφsinθ2|1⟩,r^-(θ,φ)⟷|ψ-⟩=sinθ2|0⟩-eiφcosθ2|1⟩. where (25)r^+(θ,φ)=sinθcosφe^1+sinθsinφe^2+cosθe^3, and r^-(θ,φ)=r^+(π-θ,φ+π). A direct calculation shows that r^+⋅r^-=-1 as well as ⟨ψ+|ψ-⟩=0. Figure 4 shows a geometrical picture of this result in both the unit sphere S2 immersed in the physical space (denoted by ⅅ) and the Bloch one. Figure 4:Geometrical representation of S2 and the Bloch sphere: antipodes represent orthonormal states. We may also explore Figure 4 to give some perspective on the geometry of probabilities that we spoke about before. Suppose that u^ is a unitary vector such that the system is prepared in the state (26)u^+⟷|u+⟩. We shall perform a test designated by ℳ={|ψ+⟩,|ψ-⟩}. When |u+⟩ falls in the north hemisphere (denoted by an N in Fig. 4), it is more likely to find a + in the measurement. If |u+⟩ is such that the angle between r^ and u→ is π/2, then the probabilities of getting + or - are the same and equal 1/2. To see it, we set <(u^,r^)=ω. Thus, (27)Pr(+|u^+,r^+)=12(1+cosω)=cos2(ω2) (28)Pr(-|u^+,r^-)=12(1+cos(π-ω))=sin2(ω2) Although we depict |ψ+⟩ and |ψ-⟩ falling in the same straight line, in opposite directions, they span orthogonal subspaces in ℂ2, span{|ψ+⟩}⟂=span{|ψ-⟩}. With our limited vision, the probability values in (27) and (28) would suggest sketching |ψ+⟩ and |ψ-⟩ with an angle of π/2, contrary to what was shown in the Bloch sphere of Fig. 4. Unfortunately, it is the best we can do. Previously, we have introduced the use of traces to evaluate probabilities; see (10). Let us expand this idea, which shall align our notation to the next Section. We now invert what we have done in the previous item: suppose that the system is prepared in the state ρx=|ψ+⟩⟨ψ+|, where |ψ+⟩ was defined in (22). A direct calculation shows that (29) ρ x = 1 2 ( 1 1 2 + r ^ ⋅ σ → ) . Here, 112 is the identity matrix of order 2. The calculation was carried out in the canonical representation (30) | 0 ⟩ = ( 1 0 ) , | 1 ⟩ = ( 0 1 ) . σ→=(σx,σy,σz) are the Pauli matrices and, in this case, assume the form, (31) σ x = ( 0 1 1 0 ) , σ y = ( 0 - i i 0 ) , σ z = ( 1 0 0 - 1 ) . The measurement, in turn, is associated to ℳ={|u+⟩,|u-⟩} where u^+ is obtained by a shift of ω in the θ-coordinate of r^+. In this case, (32) | u + ⟩ = cos ( θ + ω 2 ) | 0 ⟩ + e i φ sin ( θ + ω 2 ) | 1 ⟩ , (33) | u - ⟩ = sin ( θ + ω 2 ) | 0 ⟩ - e i φ cos ( θ + ω 2 ) | 1 ⟩ . A direct calculation shows the following results, (34) P r ( + | r ^ + , u ^ + ) = T r ( ρ x ℳ + ) = cos 2 ( ω 2 ) , (35) P r ( - | r ^ + , u ^ - ) = T r ( ρ x ℳ - ) = sin 2 ( ω 2 ) , where ℳ±=|u±⟩⟨u±| are orthogonal projectors. They play a role in this particular case of a broader class of operators that can be used to generalize what was defined in (34) and (35). In general, it is said that a system has a quantum behaviour when probabilities can be expressed by a Born rule, (36) P r ( a | x , y ) = T r ( ρ x ℳ y a ) , where a means the result of a test, x and y stands for preparation and measurement and ℳya is a positive operator-valued measure (POVM). Our entire analysis shows that the SG falls in this type of description, as the standard example of a quantum system, being described accordingly. . We also treat the geometry of probabilities intrinsically connected with quantum mechanics. In Section 5 5. Witnessing Dimensions in the Stern-Gerlach Until this point, we have tacitly assumed that the space of states used to make sense of the physics involved in the Stern-Gerlach experiment is two-dimensional. Incidentally, the choice of a qubit can be seen as nothing but a mere artefact. Two quantum degrees of freedom are presumably enough to explain the aggregated statistics arising out of several rounds of preparations and measurements in the Stern-Gerlach scenario. Put another way, the agreement with the probabilistic predictions could justify adopting a two-dimensional Hilbert space as it is the simplest explanation for the experiment. Nonetheless, the previous section hints that there may be a deeper link connecting our three-dimensional physical space with the space of states for qubits. The question is, can we invert this situation? Put another way, can we use only experimental data to infer the underlying space of states? This is the central problem of what is known as dimension witnesses [9, 12, 27, 28, 29]. Imagine the situation where we perform two SG in sequence, but in a way that no information about the experiment is available anywhere other than for the third party that has prepared the setup. Much in the spirit of refs. [9, 29], in this situation, the magnets can be cast as truly black-boxes that prepare and measure on demand the system under investigation. More precisely, we could say that the system is prepared in the state ρx by pressing the button x∈{1,2,…,N}. After being prepared, the system is measured by selecting a certain y∈{1,…,m}. Here, N and m enumerate the number of buttons available on each box – see Fig. 1. After a certain measurement is selected, one particular outcome is recorded: named a. The aggregated statistics coming out of this experimental setup is naturally recovered via the Born rule (37) P r ( a | x , y ) = T r ( ρ x ℳ y a ) , where {ℳya}a is a POVM for each choice of measurement button. Finally, we say that f(⋅) is a quantum dimension witness when it is upper-bounded (38) f ( P r ( a | x , y ) ) ≤ Q d for all experiments involving quantum systems of Hilbert space dimension no greater d [12]. Before moving on, let us consider an example. On the scenario so described in Fig. 1, consider the particular and simple case in which there are N possible preparations and just one measurement, that is, m = 1. We may construct a dimension witness with the average probability (39) U N = 1 N ∑ x = 1 N P r ( b = x | x ) . We can promptly obtain a superior bound on UN, as a function of d. In fact, due to the properties of the density operator ρx, (40) U N = 1 N ∑ x = 1 N T r ( ρ x ℳ x ) ≤ 1 N ∑ x T r ( ℳ x ) = d N = Q d . Thus, we are led to a dimension witness for any d<N. In our imagined Stern-Gerlach in a black-box scenario, there are m=N(N-1)2 dichotomic measurements with possible outcomes labelled ±1. A possible dimension witness can be constructed as follows [12]: (41) W N = ∑ x > x ′ | P r ( x , y ) - P r ( x ′ , y ) | 2 . We are using the notation y=(x,x′) for each measurement and Pr(x,(x,x′)):=Pr(b=1|x,y). Accordingly, ℳ(x,x′) is the associated POVM corresponding to the outcome b = 1. Due to the inequality in (40), and given that WN is a difference of probabilities, one may also write (42) W N ≤ Q d = d N . This restriction will be useful in a while. We can rewrite Eq. (41) as (43) W N = ∑ x > x ′ | Tr [ ( ρ x - ρ x ′ ) ℳ ( x , x ′ ) ] | 2 ≤ ∑ x > x ′ | D ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) | 2 , where D(ρx,ρx′) stands for the trace distance between two density operators: (44) D ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) := max ℳ { Tr [ ( ρ x - ρ x ′ ) ℳ } , and operationally represents how well two quantum states can be distinguished from each other when allowing for the most general measurement. Alternatively, the trace distance may also be related to another function of distinguishability, namely, the fidelity defined by (45) F ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) := Tr ( ρ x ρ x ′ ρ x ) . Due to the Fuch-van de Graaf inequalities [30], we have (46) 1 - D ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) ≤ F ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) ≤ 1 - D 2 ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) . The second inequality is the one that interests us the most. It allows writing (47) W N ≤ ∑ x > x ′ ( 1 - F 2 ( ρ x , ρ x ′ ) ) = ∑ x > x ′ ( 1 - | ⟨ Ψ x | Ψ x ′ ⟩ | 2 ) for pure states ρx=|Ψx⟩⟨Ψx|. Now we write (48) ∑ x > x ′ | ⟨ Ψ x | Ψ x ′ ⟩ | 2 = 1 2 ( ∑ x , x ′ | ⟨ Ψ x | Ψ x ′ ⟩ | 2 - N ) = N 2 2 T r ( Ω 2 ) - N 2 , where we define Ω:=1N∑x=1N|Ψx⟩⟨Ψx|. We can now insert the dimension of the attached Hilbert space by noting that (49) T r ( Ω 2 ) ≥ 1 d holds for any normalized state Ω. Finally, the Eqs. (47) and (48) can be used to derive the inequality below: (50) W N ≤ N 2 2 ( 1 - 1 min { d , N } ) . The compelling feature of the above witness is its tightness. It can be shown that for a suitable choice of states {ρx}x=1x as well as measurement operators ℳ(x,x′) in inequality (50) is saturated. We leverage this particular feature in our case. Working with the tightness case, the inequality in (50) becomes the following equality, (51) d N = N 2 2 ( 1 - 1 min { d , N } ) where we have used the inequalities (42) and (50). This can be seen as an equation for obtaining d given that ℳ(x,x′) is the measurement that optimally discriminates between |Ψx⟩ and |Ψx′⟩, whenever d≤N. Due to the simplicity of our experiment, we take N = 2. This substitution back in the quadratic equation in the unknown d (51) provides the unique solution d=2. This result indicates that the underlying quantum system prepared and measured in the Stern-Gerlach experiment must be two-dimensional. Our results could be stretched a bit further, it is not only the case that we are dealing with qubits in the SG experiment, in our regime, they cannot be anything else. For arbitrary N, if we could open up the black-boxes lid, and look at the inner mechanisms dictating the functioning of the boxes, we would get: (52) W N = ∑ i = 1 N | 1 + cos θ i 2 - 1 + cos θ i + 1 2 | 2 = 1 4 ∑ i = 1 N ( cos θ i - cos θ i + 1 ) 2 by a direct application of the result expressed in Eq. (4). As expected, the restriction (50) is obeyed once (i) the difference of cosines is restricted by 1 and (ii) we are setting d = 2 in the aforementioned inequality. We can also interpret N preparation buttons as selecting an arbitrary direction to the magnetic field in the SG device, and also picking the “spin up” preparing the state ρx. The second box is just another SG device as described previously, see, for example, Fig. 2. we address the modern problem of dimension witnesses within the SG experiment. Our main result consists of showing how only the statistical data extracted from a black box scenario leads to the description of the SG as a qubit. Finally, Sec. 6 6. Conclusion An entire century has passed since the seminal works of Stern and Gerlach. The motivation for this work was not only to celebrate its one-hundredth anniversary but also to explore the pedagogical potential a two-level system may provide. This way, we have used the SG device to discuss and detail many key topics in modern quantum mechanics. Let us enumerate our main results. A concatenation of two SG apparatuses may be seen as a proxy to the so-called prepare-and-measure scenario. The first device splits the incoming beam of particles in two and prevents one of the divided beams to move on. In this case, we say that the allowed beam was prepared in the state, say, ρ. The second device, in turn, measures the system previously prepared. The usual question it proposes to answer is: “Is the system in the state ρ′?”. The preparation and measurement steps assume a rather concrete form once it is obtained through the operational procedure of allowing the beam of particles to cross a spatial region fulfilled with a magnetic field. One of the central characteristics of a quantum system is its irreducible probabilistic structure [20]. In our construction, we may literally see it, with collected data from a PhET interactive simulation, see Figs. 2 and 3. Actually, the probabilities involved in our formalism can be written in terms of the angle between the magnetic fields involved in preparing and measuring the system, see (4). The geometrical representation of pure states in two-level quantum systems is depicted in the Bloch sphere. The underlying Hilbert space is spanned by the basis {|0⟩,|1⟩} and an arbitrary vector is written as the linear combination (53) | ψ ⟩ = cos θ 2 | 0 ⟩ + e i φ sin θ 2 | 1 ⟩ . Starting of from a geometry of probabilities, our construction provides a clear geometrical meaning to the parameters θ and φ in (53). They are in one-to-one correspondence with the spherical coordinates in the physical space. When we prepare a system selecting the beam with spin up after passing it through a magnetic field with direction (54) r ^ ( θ , φ ) = sin θ cos φ e ^ 1 + sin θ sin φ e ^ 2 + cos θ e ^ 3 , then the state is represented by |ψ⟩ in (53). This calculation elucidates the deep connection between the three-dimensional physical space and a qubit represented mathematically by a two-dimensional complex space. Finally, our last result concerns what is called a dimension witness. Basically, given an unknown quantum system, such formalism tries to derive bounds on the dimension of the underlying Hilbert space in order to reproduce the collected measurement data. We have shown that, with a particular black box scenario, two possible preparations are enough to reconstruct a two-dimensional space, consistent with the description of the SG as a true qubit. This conclusion confirms the profound relationship between spatial degrees of freedom and quantum mechanics. There are many more experiments and physical quantities that could be used to explore the intricate relationship between the physical space and the corresponding Hilbert space description of quantum theory, for instance, the polarization of photons. Given the celebratory occasion of the SG setup, in this paper, we are centring our attention exclusively on that physical experiment; we shall address this connection (physical space with Hilbert space) elsewhere, though. At last, in [31], the authors typify quantum correlations as a function of local symmetries. As stated, it indicates a foundational connection between quantum theory and space-time itself. is left for the conclusions.
2. Simulating a Prepare-and-measure Scenario
The so-called prepare-and-measure scenario basically consists of two boxes [9[9] R. Gallego, N. Brunner, C. Hadley and A. Acín, Physical Review Letters 1051, 230501 (2010)., 10[10] C. de Gois, G. Moreno, R. Nery, S. Brito, R. Chaves and R. Rabelo, PRX Quantum 2, 030311 (2021)., 18[18] C. Duarte and B. Amaral, Journal of Mathematical Physics 59, 062202 (2018).]. The first one has Nx buttons that prepare the system in a state under demand. The second box has other Ny buttons that perform measurements, providing different outcomes labelled by . Fig. 1 depicts this idea.
When no more information about the nature of the physical systems involved in this scenario is available to the experimentalist, the only thing they can do is describe it through a set of conditional probabilities of getting an outcome a, after preparing the system with x and measuring y.
Note that this is exactly what a sequence of two SG devices provides. In fact, to push a button x means, operationally, to select a direction to the magnetic field that separates the flux of particles in two, together with blocking one of the resultant split beams, while the other is free to move on (into the measurement device). Care must be taken when we say “the direction” of the magnetic field in this case. One possible realization of the inhomogeneous magnetic field of the SG device is given by
where is the basis of the physical space of displacement vectors ), with coordinates x, y and z [19[19] L.M. Gaio, D.R.T. de Barros and B.F. Rizzuti, Rev. Bras. Ensino Física 41, e20180295 (2019).]. B0 is the component of in the z direction. represents small deviations in the sense that and are much smaller than . It guarantees that (i) we have an inhomogeneous magnetic field and (ii) , as expected. In this case, we say that the magnetic field points towards the z direction, by an abuse of notation. We may also realize what the y-button represents. It defines another direction of a magnetic field, that, once again, may split the income beam into two. In one of the exits, there is a wall to stop the outcome beam. On the other, though, there is a Geiger-count type detector. This is the spirit of what once was called a “Yes-No” experiment or proposition – the core of older quantum systems descriptions based on the propositional calculus [20[20] J.M. Jauch, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Addison-Wesley, Reading, 1968).]. In modern terminology, we call it a projective measurement (on a qubit) or a test [21[21] B. Amaral, A.T. Baraviera and M.O.T. Cunha, Mecânica Quântica para Matemáticos em Formação (IMPA, Rio de Janeiro, 2011).]. It is specified by a set . If we measure the qubit prepared in the state , then the possible outcomes are or +, interpreted here as being blocked by the wall or counted by the detector. This structure may also be rephrased, noting that y can be interpreted not only as a measurement but also as a preparation of states. Hence, the measurement of the second box can be restated by the (yes-no) question: once the system is prepared in the state , is the system in the state ? Questions of the form: “What is the state of the system?” seems to be difficult to be approached experimentally [22[22] O. Guhne and G. Toth, Physics Reports 474, 1 (2009)., 23[23] M. Cramer, M.B. Plenio, S.T. Flammia and R. So, Nature Communications 1, 149 (2010)., 24[24] Z. Hradil, Physical Review A, 55, R1561–R1564 (1997).].
3. Experimental Facts Concerning the SG Experiment
The basic experimental fact concerning the sequence of two SG devices in the prepare-and-measure scenario is related to a conditional probability. We will use the following notation. Each x (or y) button of preparation (or measure) is defined by a direction () in the physical space, that orients the magnetic field. Moreover, it also selects either one (+) or the other () split beam (both in x, allowing one of the scattered beams to head into the measuring device and y, to set the detector). So, we define
This notation is explored1 1 We extensively use the PhET interactive simulations available at https://phet.colorado.edu/pt/simulation/legacy/stern-gerlach. in Fig. 2. In this case, selects the beam with spin up in the z direction. Else, counts the atoms that fire the wall with spin up in a direction rotated by of the first magnetic field. This figure also shows a particular example of an experimental fact,
To see this, we have plotted the graph in Fig. 3, with a repeated sequence of SG experiments, keeping fixed while varying . The curious result is consistent with (4). The data used to plot the graph was, once again, collected using the SG PhET interactive simulations: it is possible to define the angle between the magnetic fields in both devices.
Before moving on to complete the construction of states in this particular experiment, let us discuss a peculiar feature of a concatenation of SG devices, which is related to the concept of reproducibility of tests. Let us set a sequence of two SG devices, fully characterized by . We find that . In other words, the question of having the states prepared and measured by the same magnetic field is answered with of certainty. Furthermore, we could insert another box after the two ones, asking the same question. The answer would be “yes” repeatedly. Now comes the tricky step, which has no immediate classical counterpart [25[25] D. Jennings and M. Leifer, Contemporary Physics 57, 60 (2015).]. Let us consider three SG devices, characterized by, say, , and , respectively. Each box may be interpreted as either prepare or measuring device. This is so because the income beam, as previously discussed, is divided by two. The first and the third are the same. However, the second test destroys the preparation performed by the first box. Thus, the answer in the third one is not responded to repeatedly. In this sense, the first and second tests are called incompatible. Conversely, two distinct tests, say and are called compatible whenever the test , applied in between two repetitions of , does not affect the reproducibility of . We point out that this situation is drastically different from its classical counterpart. In fact, for a spinning top, with angular momentum , one could obtain, say and simultaneously. Here, I stands for the moment of inertia, and is the corresponding angular velocity [8[8] J.J. Sakurai and J. Napolitano, Modern quantum mechanics (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017), 2 ed.].
4. Bloch Sphere Unveiled
The discussion presented so far hasn’t revealed the proper representation of states in the SG experiment. The incompatibility of tests discussed before is just a piece of evidence for its quantum description. Besides that, the division of the income beam in two indicates that we could use a two-dimensional Hilbert space to fully represent the experiment. Let us assume, then, that the state of space is just , with vectors denoted by the standard Dirac notation. This ad hoc imposition leads to the correct conditional probability (4) through a Born rule, to be presented in a while, see (34) and (35). We will also construct the Bloch sphere here. To do so, we divide our tasks into subsections. In the first one, we try to explore a liaison between the geometry of Hilbert spaces and probabilities. Then, we direct our efforts to the Bloch sphere itself. Finally, a list of comments will be given.
4.1. Geometry of probabilities
The parametrization given in (1) reflects a clean geometrical meaning in terms of the preparation of states. In fact, the pair uniquely describes the state prepared by
that is, the radial arbitrary direction in spherical coordinates in the physical space that indicates the magnetic field orientation. As usual, is the canonical basis of .
Let us clarify this point. As mentioned before, the two split beams indicate that is a good candidate for the space of states. Let us choose a basis in . By pressing the x-button of preparation, we select a particular direction in space to point the magnetic field as well as one of the scattered beams. So, we take
It means that the vectors and represent the two possible preparations. These two possible choices mean that the system may bear excluding properties (i.e., of being selected by x1 or x2 in (6)). So, we associate a property of the system to a subspace in the state of space. There is one way to describe what is the probability of a system to posses a particular property: we look at the projection of the state vector onto the corresponding subspace. This geometry of probabilities asks for a inner-product in , . For our case, if the system is prepared in the state , it should have no component in the subspace spanned by . In fact, the properties of being selected by x1 or x2 are excluded. Thus, , which also implies that can be taken as a basis for , as they are linearly independent. Along with the lines above, for a general state vector
where represents the probability of the system to be measured by as well as by , owing to the geometry of probabilities so constructed.
Mathematically, we project on the corresponding subspace and take the square. That is, if , then
Instead of and , one could take projectors to represent states,
or even . The probabilities estimated in (8) assume the form
In this case, one or the other option will be answered. So, has a clear meaning in terms of probabilities. Another possible geometrical origin to quantum probabilities (and their difference to the classical ones) may be found in [26[26] C.J. Isham, Lectures on Quantum Theory: Mathematical and Structural Foundations (Imperial College Press, London, 1995).].
4.2. Geometrical interpretation to the Blochsphere
Our final task consists of finding the complex coefficients and in terms of the duple that defines uniquely, see (5).
Firstly, we may guess what are the states corresponding to the preparations . According to , the prepared states oscillate when asked about . Thus,
and , as expected (the properties of being prepared by and are excluding). The set could also be taken as a basis for . The change can be seen as a rotation of (or a unitary transformation in the case of complex vector spaces). Likewise, we can “rotate” in the complex state of spaces both and by a factor to generate the basis . First, we write
Noting that a global phase factor is irrelevant (in the sense of preserving probabilities), we finally define
As in the case of and , is also formed by orthonormal vectors and
They generate the correct oscillations of in the probabilities,
With the basis , and we are in position to obtain the coefficients and in (7), such that and is an arbitrary direction in the physical space.
Invoking once again that the conditional probability (4) is only a function of the angles between the magnetic field vectors involved in preparing and measuring, we have
The last equality holds due to the geometry of probabilities constructed so far. So, . Since a global phase factor does not influence probabilities, we hide in .
Following this spirit and knowing that
we have
Since , we find,
Analogously,
implies
If we now gather all the pieces, then and
completing our final objective of operationally constructing (1). To avoid a lengthy discussion here, we leave the next subsection for general comments and discussions concerning our approach.
4.3. General comments and discussions
-
Starting from a three-dimensional physical space, we may construct a two-dimensional state of spaces. Actually, we assumed that we had a two-dimensional Hilbert space. This assumption has led us to a theoretical construction that fits perfectly with the experimental data available. What can be said about the inverse? The existence of qubits necessarily needs a three-dimensional space?
-
Our construction has shown a geometrical significance to the pair used to parametrize state vectors, given by (22). If the pair runs values in the standard domain and , then we cover the unit sphere, and so does over what is called the Bloch sphere. With a fixed , the two vectors with and are connected with the following states,
This calculation indicates a general result: antipodes on the unit sphere are related to orthonormal states. In fact, in physical space, the pairs and generate a couple of antipodes and, as stated, we have where and . A direct calculation shows that as well as . Figure 4 shows a geometrical picture of this result in both the unit sphere immersed in the physical space (denoted by ) and the Bloch one.Figure 4:
Geometrical representation of and the Bloch sphere: antipodes represent orthonormal states.
-
Previously, we have introduced the use of traces to evaluate probabilities; see (10). Let us expand this idea, which shall align our notation to the next Section. We now invert what we have done in the previous item: suppose that the system is prepared in the state , where was defined in (22). A direct calculation shows that
Here, is the identity matrix of order 2. The calculation was carried out in the canonical representation
are the Pauli matrices and, in this case, assume the form,
The measurement, in turn, is associated to where is obtained by a shift of in the -coordinate of . In this case,
A direct calculation shows the following results,
where are orthogonal projectors. They play a role in this particular case of a broader class of operators that can be used to generalize what was defined in (34) and (35). In general, it is said that a system has a quantum behaviour when probabilities can be expressed by a Born rule,
where a means the result of a test, x and y stands for preparation and measurement and is a positive operator-valued measure (POVM). Our entire analysis shows that the SG falls in this type of description, as the standard example of a quantum system, being described accordingly.
5. Witnessing Dimensions in the Stern-Gerlach
Until this point, we have tacitly assumed that the space of states used to make sense of the physics involved in the Stern-Gerlach experiment is two-dimensional. Incidentally, the choice of a qubit can be seen as nothing but a mere artefact. Two quantum degrees of freedom are presumably enough to explain the aggregated statistics arising out of several rounds of preparations and measurements in the Stern-Gerlach scenario. Put another way, the agreement with the probabilistic predictions could justify adopting a two-dimensional Hilbert space as it is the simplest explanation for the experiment.
Nonetheless, the previous section hints that there may be a deeper link connecting our three-dimensional physical space with the space of states for qubits. The question is, can we invert this situation? Put another way, can we use only experimental data to infer the underlying space of states? This is the central problem of what is known as dimension witnesses [9[9] R. Gallego, N. Brunner, C. Hadley and A. Acín, Physical Review Letters 1051, 230501 (2010)., 12[12] N. Brunner, M. Navascués and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. Lett. 110, 150501 (2013)., 27[27] Y. Cai, J.-D. Bancal, J. Romero and V. Scarani, Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical 49, 305301 (2016)., 28[28] K.F. Pál and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. A 96, 022123 (2017)., 29[29] N. Brunner, S. Pironio, A. Acin, N. Gisin, A.A. Méthot and V. Scarani, Phys. Rev. Lett. 100, 210503 (2008).].
Imagine the situation where we perform two SG in sequence, but in a way that no information about the experiment is available anywhere other than for the third party that has prepared the setup. Much in the spirit of refs. [9[9] R. Gallego, N. Brunner, C. Hadley and A. Acín, Physical Review Letters 1051, 230501 (2010)., 29[29] N. Brunner, S. Pironio, A. Acin, N. Gisin, A.A. Méthot and V. Scarani, Phys. Rev. Lett. 100, 210503 (2008).], in this situation, the magnets can be cast as truly black-boxes that prepare and measure on demand the system under investigation. More precisely, we could say that the system is prepared in the state by pressing the button . After being prepared, the system is measured by selecting a certain . Here, N and m enumerate the number of buttons available on each box – see Fig. 1. After a certain measurement is selected, one particular outcome is recorded: named a. The aggregated statistics coming out of this experimental setup is naturally recovered via the Born rule
where is a POVM for each choice of measurement button. Finally, we say that is a quantum dimension witness when it is upper-bounded
for all experiments involving quantum systems of Hilbert space dimension no greater d [12[12] N. Brunner, M. Navascués and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. Lett. 110, 150501 (2013).]. Before moving on, let us consider an example. On the scenario so described in Fig. 1, consider the particular and simple case in which there are N possible preparations and just one measurement, that is, m = 1. We may construct a dimension witness with the average probability
We can promptly obtain a superior bound on UN, as a function of d. In fact, due to the properties of the density operator ,
Thus, we are led to a dimension witness for any .
In our imagined Stern-Gerlach in a black-box scenario, there are dichotomic measurements with possible outcomes labelled . A possible dimension witness can be constructed as follows [12[12] N. Brunner, M. Navascués and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. Lett. 110, 150501 (2013).]:
We are using the notation for each measurement and . Accordingly, is the associated POVM corresponding to the outcome b = 1. Due to the inequality in (40), and given that WN is a difference of probabilities, one may also write
This restriction will be useful in a while.
We can rewrite Eq. (41) as
where stands for the trace distance between two density operators:
and operationally represents how well two quantum states can be distinguished from each other when allowing for the most general measurement. Alternatively, the trace distance may also be related to another function of distinguishability, namely, the fidelity defined by
Due to the Fuch-van de Graaf inequalities [30[30] J. Watrous, The Theory of Quantum Information (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018).], we have
The second inequality is the one that interests us the most. It allows writing
for pure states . Now we write
where we define .
We can now insert the dimension of the attached Hilbert space by noting that
holds for any normalized state . Finally, the Eqs. (47) and (48) can be used to derive the inequality below:
The compelling feature of the above witness is its tightness. It can be shown that for a suitable choice of states as well as measurement operators in inequality (50) is saturated. We leverage this particular feature in our case.
Working with the tightness case, the inequality in (50) becomes the following equality,
where we have used the inequalities (42) and (50). This can be seen as an equation for obtaining d given that is the measurement that optimally discriminates between and , whenever . Due to the simplicity of our experiment, we take N = 2. This substitution back in the quadratic equation in the unknown d (51) provides the unique solution d=2. This result indicates that the underlying quantum system prepared and measured in the Stern-Gerlach experiment must be two-dimensional. Our results could be stretched a bit further, it is not only the case that we are dealing with qubits in the SG experiment, in our regime, they cannot be anything else.
For arbitrary N, if we could open up the black-boxes lid, and look at the inner mechanisms dictating the functioning of the boxes, we would get:
by a direct application of the result expressed in Eq. (4). As expected, the restriction (50) is obeyed once (i) the difference of cosines is restricted by 1 and (ii) we are setting d = 2 in the aforementioned inequality.
We can also interpret N preparation buttons as selecting an arbitrary direction to the magnetic field in the SG device, and also picking the “spin up” preparing the state . The second box is just another SG device as described previously, see, for example, Fig. 2.
6. Conclusion
An entire century has passed since the seminal works of Stern and Gerlach. The motivation for this work was not only to celebrate its one-hundredth anniversary but also to explore the pedagogical potential a two-level system may provide. This way, we have used the SG device to discuss and detail many key topics in modern quantum mechanics. Let us enumerate our main results.
-
A concatenation of two SG apparatuses may be seen as a proxy to the so-called prepare-and-measure scenario. The first device splits the incoming beam of particles in two and prevents one of the divided beams to move on. In this case, we say that the allowed beam was prepared in the state, say, . The second device, in turn, measures the system previously prepared. The usual question it proposes to answer is: “Is the system in the state ?”. The preparation and measurement steps assume a rather concrete form once it is obtained through the operational procedure of allowing the beam of particles to cross a spatial region fulfilled with a magnetic field.
-
One of the central characteristics of a quantum system is its irreducible probabilistic structure [20[20] J.M. Jauch, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Addison-Wesley, Reading, 1968).]. In our construction, we may literally see it, with collected data from a PhET interactive simulation, see Figs. 2 and 3. Actually, the probabilities involved in our formalism can be written in terms of the angle between the magnetic fields involved in preparing and measuring the system, see (4).
-
The geometrical representation of pure states in two-level quantum systems is depicted in the Bloch sphere. The underlying Hilbert space is spanned by the basis and an arbitrary vector is written as the linear combination
Starting of from a geometry of probabilities, our construction provides a clear geometrical meaning to the parameters and in (53). They are in one-to-one correspondence with the spherical coordinates in the physical space. When we prepare a system selecting the beam with spin up after passing it through a magnetic field with direction
then the state is represented by in (53). This calculation elucidates the deep connection between the three-dimensional physical space and a qubit represented mathematically by a two-dimensional complex space.
-
Finally, our last result concerns what is called a dimension witness. Basically, given an unknown quantum system, such formalism tries to derive bounds on the dimension of the underlying Hilbert space in order to reproduce the collected measurement data. We have shown that, with a particular black box scenario, two possible preparations are enough to reconstruct a two-dimensional space, consistent with the description of the SG as a true qubit. This conclusion confirms the profound relationship between spatial degrees of freedom and quantum mechanics. There are many more experiments and physical quantities that could be used to explore the intricate relationship between the physical space and the corresponding Hilbert space description of quantum theory, for instance, the polarization of photons. Given the celebratory occasion of the SG setup, in this paper, we are centring our attention exclusively on that physical experiment; we shall address this connection (physical space with Hilbert space) elsewhere, though. At last, in [31[31] A.J.P. Garner, M. Krumm and M.P. Müller, Phys. Rev. Research 2, 013112 (2020).], the authors typify quantum correlations as a function of local symmetries. As stated, it indicates a foundational connection between quantum theory and space-time itself.
Acknowledgments
CD thanks the hospitality of the Institute for Quantum Studies at Chapman University. The authors thank immensely the anonymous referee for the valuable suggestions. This work has been supported by Programa Institucional de Bolsas de Iniciação Científica – XXXII BIC/Universidade Federal de Juiz de Fora – 2019/2020, project number 46729 (Programa Institucional de Bolsas de Iniciação Científica – XXXIV BIC/Universidade Federal de Juiz de Fora – 2021/2022, project number 48982). This research was partially supported by the National Research, Development and Innovation Office of Hungary (NKFIH) through the Quantum Information National Laboratory of Hungary and through the grant FK 135220. This research was also supported by the Fetzer Franklin Fund of the John E. Fetzer Memorial Trust and by grant number FQXi-RFP-IPW-1905 from the Foundational Questions Institute and Fetzer Franklin Fund, a donor advised fund of Silicon Valley Community Foundation.
Supplementary material
The following online material is available for this article: Appendix A: The geometry of indistinguishable states.
References
-
[1]O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 7, 253 (1921).
-
[2]W. Gerlach and O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 8, 111 (1921).
-
[3]W. Gerlach and O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 9, 349 (1922).
-
[4]W. Gerlach and O. Stern, Zeitschrift für Physik 9, 353 (1922).
-
[5]G.G. Gomes and M. Pietrocola, Revista Brasileira de Ensino de Física 33, 2604 (2011).
-
[6]T.-Y. Wu, A. Kumar, F. Giraldo and D. S. Weiss, Nature Physics 15, 538 (2019).
-
[7]C. Cohen-Tannoudji, B. Diu and F. Laloë, Quantum mechanics. Basic concepts, tools, and applications (Wiley-VCH, Weinheim, 2020), v.1, 2 ed.
-
[8]J.J. Sakurai and J. Napolitano, Modern quantum mechanics (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017), 2 ed.
-
[9]R. Gallego, N. Brunner, C. Hadley and A. Acín, Physical Review Letters 1051, 230501 (2010).
-
[10]C. de Gois, G. Moreno, R. Nery, S. Brito, R. Chaves and R. Rabelo, PRX Quantum 2, 030311 (2021).
-
[11]M.A. Nielsen and I.L. Chuang, Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2011), 10 ed.
-
[12]N. Brunner, M. Navascués and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. Lett. 110, 150501 (2013).
-
[13]N. Brunner, D. Cavalcanti, S. Pironio, V. Scarani and S. Wehner, Reviews of Modern Physics 86, 419 (2014).
-
[14]C. Manogue, AIP Conference Proceedings 1413, 55 (2012).
-
[15]N.L. Harshman, American Journal of Physics 87, 237 (2019).
-
[16]C.H. Bennett, G. Brassard, C. Crépeau, R. Jozsa, A. Peres and W.K. Wootters, Physical Review Letters 70, 1895 (1993).
-
[17]C.H. Bennett and G. Brassard, Proceedings of IEEE International Conference on Computers, Systems and Signal Processing 175, 8 (1984)
-
[18]C. Duarte and B. Amaral, Journal of Mathematical Physics 59, 062202 (2018).
-
[19]L.M. Gaio, D.R.T. de Barros and B.F. Rizzuti, Rev. Bras. Ensino Física 41, e20180295 (2019).
-
[20]J.M. Jauch, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (Addison-Wesley, Reading, 1968).
-
[21]B. Amaral, A.T. Baraviera and M.O.T. Cunha, Mecânica Quântica para Matemáticos em Formação (IMPA, Rio de Janeiro, 2011).
-
[22]O. Guhne and G. Toth, Physics Reports 474, 1 (2009).
-
[23]M. Cramer, M.B. Plenio, S.T. Flammia and R. So, Nature Communications 1, 149 (2010).
-
[24]Z. Hradil, Physical Review A, 55, R1561–R1564 (1997).
-
[25]D. Jennings and M. Leifer, Contemporary Physics 57, 60 (2015).
-
[26]C.J. Isham, Lectures on Quantum Theory: Mathematical and Structural Foundations (Imperial College Press, London, 1995).
-
[27]Y. Cai, J.-D. Bancal, J. Romero and V. Scarani, Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical 49, 305301 (2016).
-
[28]K.F. Pál and T. Vértesi, Phys. Rev. A 96, 022123 (2017).
-
[29]N. Brunner, S. Pironio, A. Acin, N. Gisin, A.A. Méthot and V. Scarani, Phys. Rev. Lett. 100, 210503 (2008).
-
[30]J. Watrous, The Theory of Quantum Information (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2018).
-
[31]A.J.P. Garner, M. Krumm and M.P. Müller, Phys. Rev. Research 2, 013112 (2020).
-
1
We extensively use the PhET interactive simulations available at https://phet.colorado.edu/pt/simulation/legacy/stern-gerlach.
Publication Dates
-
Publication in this collection
31 Mar 2023 -
Date of issue
2023
History
-
Received
08 Aug 2022 -
Reviewed
01 Feb 2023 -
Accepted
03 Feb 2023