Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

Reflections on the main epistemological currents regarding health sciences

LETTER TO THE EDITOR

Reflections on the main epistemological currents regarding health sciences

Technological progress in science is remarkable and undeniable, especially regarding the health area. Financial investments in this sector have exponentially grown in relation to the early 20th century, and even work-up and therapeutic methods available to health professionals are based on scientific statements, theories and laws.1 However, such technological increment was only possible thanks to deep philosophical reflections throughout time and that were often conflicting.2,3 It becomes relevant to know the main philosophical conceptions and their influence on the evolution of health sciences, which allows a better understanding of their dynamism and fallibility.1-3

Philosophy can be defined as the study characterized by human intention of widening its knowledge about the reality, in order to comprehend it as a whole, whether in materialized and/or imaginary real "Being", whether in the definition of instruments able to corroborate a thought, a fundament, a law or a principle. A digest, defined as a detailed description about facts, between philosophy correlations and the scientific method, allows us to see that throughout time the philosophical thinking was established in different currents with peculiar definitions and foundations, which, however, as a common sense, harmonize and complete such differences.2,4,5

Despite the line of thought called logical positivism or logical empiricism having been initially created by mathematicians and physicists in Austria around 1920, Comte was its main character. Comte's positivism was based on the principles of logic and mathematics as foundations for knowledge or confirmation of hypotheses, since they established rules independent of experience. For Comte, even general statements and scientific laws could be obtained based on observation or induction of a phenomenon, whether it was natural and/or experimental.2,6

However, positivists faced several criticisms that were based on the fact that every scientific observation is immersed in theories, such as, for example, measuring temperature with a mercury thermometer, whose principle is that all metals dilate when their temperature increases. And, due to the possibility that observations could incorporate fallible theories, it would not be possible to consider them as safe sources to build knowledge, neither as a solid foundation for scientific development.

Validity of inductive reasoning was also questioned, since induction is not a deductive argument and, therefore, is not logically valid. The main example is that before the first confirmation of the existence of black swans, it was believed that all swans were white. Induction could not, therefore, be justified neither by logic, nor by experience.2 Even the practice of scientific evidence stresses that one should be careful about conclusions based on personal experience, independently of professional population and of the individual's scientific knowledge.1

From those reflections Popper's critical rationalism was developed, based on the attempt of achieving truth about the scientific method and general knowledge without only involving induction, which could be possible using as principle that observations could only be used to refute (deny, reprove) general statements, not being possible to evolve any knowledge whose theories were not open to criticism and refutation. Popper also defined that statements potentially able to contradict a law or theory would be called potential falsifiers and that the group of such falsifiers would serve as a parameter for the empirical content of the theory: the more the theory "prohibited" them (they are now identified as exclusion criteria), the more it would tell us about the world.2,7 Therefore, scientific criticism is crucial for scientific progress.1,8,9

Finally, Popper claimed that the level of corroboration (acceptance) increased when we moved from older to more recent theories and researches in the following manner: search for knowledge started with the formulation of hypotheses that aimed at solving problems and that should resist the most rigid tests as possible. In case they did not resist, hypotheses would be refuted and replaced by others, which would also be tested and so forth.2,7,10 Hence the importance of continuity in research, of detailed method description, of statistical analysis of results and study publication.2,7,11 However, it is important to understand that, even after they are confirmed, hypotheses should be accepted as temporary solutions for a given problem and that, similarly, their refutation will always be conjectural, since there might have been an error in observation, experiment or even a random error.2-4,9

Popper was criticized by the current called "the new philosophy of science," represented by Kuhn, Lakatos and Feyerabend, who claimed: "statements and tests are impregnated with theories; we usually test complex theoretical systems, and not isolated hypotheses."2,4,12,13 For Thomas Kuhn, in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), the mere observation of a given theory incompatibility or refutation would not justify its abandonment by the researcher; on the contrary, he should analyze maturely the criticisms and unconfirmed results to save his theory, only justifying such attitude when faced with the following facts: significant discrepancy between predicted and expected, accumulation of anomalies found or that prevented its practical application and that resisted for a long time, even after test repetition or change. Confronted with such phenomena, the researcher would have a scientific crisis, which, in its turn, would foster search for a new paradigm.1,2,4,7,8,12 Also according to Kuhn, there is a change in paradigm in those "scientific revolutions," and although the world does not change after a change in paradigm, the scientist begins to see and work in a different world."2,12

On the other hand, for Imre Lakatos (1922-1974) it would always be possible to prevent one theory from being refuted, as long as changes were made only in auxiliary hypotheses, maintaining its core intact, which is actually one of the characteristics of a line of research.1,2 For Lakatos, the history of science shows that theories are not abandoned, even after being refuted. Similarly to Thomas Kuhn, Lakatos claimed that a scientific theory can be rehabilitated at any time, as long as some researchers keep working on it.2,4,10,13 This is one of the reasons to experience throughout time scientific reasoning and conducts that have already been used in past times. However, it is essential to critically analyze the justification of trying again something that could not be explained and/or approved before, considering whether there is plausibility in the proposal brought back to life.1,2,4,9

But it was Feyerabend who dared to challenge the logic of scientific harmony. With great exclusiveness, he created the anarchic conception of science by claiming that it does not have its own method, a rigid rule, neither it is a rational activity, but an anarchic entrepreneurship in which any previously proposed methodological rule, including rules of logic, were at some time violated by scientists, representing a crucial stage to make science progress.2,4 Nevertheless, at the same time he was contradicting Kuhn, saying that he could not see a place for the objective criteria of assessments, he corroborated his predecessors by stating that one should not abandon a theory when faced with refutations.2,4,12,13 Despite Feyerabend's apparent radicalism, the history of medicine partially corroborates the anarchism proposed by him.10 However, attitudes that go against current bioethical principles are no longer accepted by everyone involved in scientific progress.8,9

Finally, sociology of science also stood out, focusing on the great influence existing between social factors and scientific activity, according to which it is common that evaluations, awards and publications of papers and researches in relevant scientific journals are determined not only by their scientific contents, but also by social factors. The "victory" of these works would then be a result of a dispute or negotiation between scientists, institutions or even countries.2,4

The statements of sociology of knowledge were also quite criticized by different sectors, since it is hard to accept that the success of science is only based on negotiations and social and political interests. In addition, it is known that one of the ways to achieve fame, professional success and funds is by producing methodologically correct studies.1,2,14 But such information obligatorily refers us to a deep reflection on this theme.

It can then be perceived that the different philosophical currents about the scientific method allowed a wide space for a mature and highly constructive debate of science itself and that changes in paradigms have always occurred and will always occur. Not investing or escaping from scientific rigor implies abdicating the possibility of correcting errors, thus abdicating the true spirit of science itself.

References

Manuscript received August 10, 2007, accepted September 12, 2007.

Ricardo Costa-Val

Titular member, SBACV. President, SBACV-MG, 2008-2009. MSc. and PhD, Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais (UFMG), Belo Horizonte, MG, Brazil. Professor, Graduation: Academic Master's in Health Sciences, Universidade Vale do Rio Verde (UninCor), Betim, MG, Brazil, and Instituto de Previdência dos Servidores do Estado de Minas Gerais (IPSEMG), Belo Horizonte, MG, Brazil.Address: Rua Boa Esperança, 341/101, Bairro Carmo, CEP 30310-730 - Belo Horizonte, MG, Brazil.Telephone: (31) 9972.6066. E-mail: ricardocostaval@hotmail.com

Maria Cristina Marques

Nursing Administrative Manager, Hospital Galba Ortopédico, Fundação Hospitalar do Estado de Minas Gerais (FHEMIG), Belo Horizonte, MG, Brazil. Graduate student, Auditing in Health Systems, Faculdade São Camilo, Belo Horizonte, MG, Brazil. Coordinating Nurse of the International, Multicenter Clinical Trial (Phase 3) "F7 Trauma-1711" under responsibility of Novo Nordisk® , unit Hospital de Pronto Socorro João XXIII, FHEMIG, Belo Horizonte, MG, Brazil.

  • 1. Drummond JP, Silva E, Coutinho M. Medicina baseada em evidências: novo paradigma assistencial e pedagógico. 2Ş ed. São Paulo: Atheneu; 2004.
  • 2. Alves-Mazzotti AJ, Gewandsznajder F. A pesquisa científica. In: Alves-Mazzotti AJ, Gewandsznajder F. O método nas ciências naturais e sociais. São Paulo: Pioneira; 1999. p. 65-84.
  • 3. Tanaka OY, Melo C. Reflexões sobre a avaliação em serviços de saúde e a adoção das abordagens qualitativa e quantitativa. In: Bosi MLM, Mercado FJ, organizadores. Pesquisa qualitativa de serviços de saúde.Rio de Janeiro: Vozes; 2004. p. 121-36.
  • 4. Francelin MM. Ciência, senso comum e revoluções científicas: ressonâncias e paradoxos. Ci Inf. 2004;33:26-34.
  • 5. Ferreira ABH. Novo Aurélio Século XXI®: o dicionário da língua portuguesa. Rio de Janeiro: Nova Fronteira/Lexikon Informática; 2005.
  • 6. Comte A. Discurso preliminar sobre o espírito positivo. Edição eletrônica: Ridendo Catigad Mores. Disponível em: http://sociologia.incubadora.fapesp.br/portal/publicacoes-1/apostilas/espirito-positivo-comte.pdf Acessado: 28/07/2007.
  • 7. Papineau D. Methodology: the elements of philosophy of science. In: Grayling AC, editor. Philosophy: a guide through the subject. London: Oxford University; 2000. p. 123-80.
  • 8. Costa-Val R. A iminente mudança de paradigma na relação entre a indústria farmacêutica e a medicina. J Vasc Bras. 2007;6:104-6.
  • 9. El Dib RP. Como praticar a medicina baseada em evidências [editorial]. J Vasc Bras. 2007;6:1-4.
  • 10. Margotta, R. The history of medicine. New York: Smithmark; 1996.
  • 11. Yoshida WB. A nossa produção científica invisível. J Vasc Bras. 2005;4:113.
  • 12. Assis JEP. Kuhn e as ciências sociais [dissertação]. São Paulo: FFLCH-USP; 1991.
  • 13. Lakatos I. Criticism of the proof-analysis by counterexamples which are global but not local: the problem of rigour. In: Lakatos I. Proofs and refutations: the logic of mathematical discovery. London: Cambridge University; 1976. p. 42-50.
  • 14. Drumond JGF. Os vinte anos da FAPEMIG. J Estado de Minas. Seção Opinião, março 2006, p. 11.
  • Reflexões sobre as principais linhas epistemológicas pertinentes às ciências da saúde

    É notório e indiscutível o progresso tecnológico da ciência, particularmente na área da saúde. O investimento financeiro gasto nesse setor cresceu exponencialmente em relação ao começo do século passado, e os próprios métodos propedêuticos e terapêuticos disponíveis aos profissionais da saúde possuem como base enunciados, teorias e leis científicas1. Entretanto, tal incremento tecnológico só foi possível graças a profundas reflexões filosóficas que existiram ao longo do tempo e que foram muitas vezes conflitantes2,3. Torna-se relevante conhecer as principais concepções filosóficas e sua influência na evolução das ciências da saúde, o que permite uma melhor compreensão sobre o dinamismo e a falibilidade destas1-3.
  • Publication Dates

    • Publication in this collection
      07 Feb 2008
    • Date of issue
      Dec 2007
    Sociedade Brasileira de Angiologia e de Cirurgia Vascular (SBACV) Rua Estela, 515, bloco E, conj. 21, Vila Mariana, CEP04011-002 - São Paulo, SP, Tel.: (11) 5084.3482 / 5084.2853 - Porto Alegre - RS - Brazil
    E-mail: secretaria@sbacv.org.br