Acessibilidade / Reportar erro

CHANCE (τύχη), FATE (εἱµαρµένη), 'WHATDEPENDS ON US' (τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν) AND PROVIDENCE (πρόνοια) IN PLUTARCH'S QUAESTIONES CONVIVALES

ABSTRACT

One of the many philosophical issues discussed throughout Plutarch's Quaestiones convivales (QC) has to do with the origin and inner structure of the universe, i.e., cosmological discussions. It would be impossible to discuss in detail every passage of the treatise that deals with cosmological issues. Therefore, I chose to limit my analysis to the concepts of chance (τύχη), fate (εἱμαρμένη), ‘what depends on us ’ (τὸ ἐφ' ἡμῖν), and providence (πρóνoια). My purpose is to explain these concepts in the QC and to extract from them a cosmological doctrine.

Keywords:
Chance; Fate; ‘WhatDepends on us’; Free-Will; Providence; Plutarch.

RESUMO

Entre os vários problemas filosóficos discutidos ao longo das Quaestiones Convivales (QC) de Plutarco, um deles tem que ver com a origem e com a estrutura do universo, isto é, discussões de cariz cosmológico. Seria impossível comentar em detalhe todas as passagens do tratado sobre questões cosmológicas. Por isso, preferi limitar a análise aos conceitos de acaso (τύχη), destino (εἱμαρμένη), 'o que depende de nós' (τὸ ἐφ' ἡμῖν) eprovidência (πρóνoια). O meu objetivo é explicar estes conceitos nas QC e deles inferir uma doutrina cosmológica.

Palavras-chave:
Acaso; destino; 'o que depende de nós'; livre-arbítrio; providência; Plutarco.

1. Introduction

The Quaestiones convivales, or Συµποσιακά, are the longest work among the group of treatises known as Moralia.1 1 Pages 612-748 (the whole vol. VIII) in the Stephanus edition. From now on, the Quaestiones convivales will be referred as QC. For a global analysis and bibliography on this treatise vide Ferreira et al. (2009); Klotz & Oikonomopoulou (2011). This treatise belongs to an ancient literary genre that had strong sociological connotations. Ever since the Homeric Poems, many ancient Greek authors, from Archaic poets to Attic writers (including those that imitated them in the following centuries), composed what we now call sympotic works. Either fictional or historical (or both), these texts aimed to represent the social institution of conversation while drinking wine.2 2 For a general view on the symposion as a social institution vide Murray (1990); Orfanos & Carrière (2003); Hobden (2013). Plato's Symposium is surely the most famous example, and it also represents a paradigm shift on this genre.3 3 On sympotic works before Plato vide Bowie (1993); and Romeri (2002) on works after Plato. As Xenophontos (2016XENOPHONTOS, S. “Ethical Education in Plutarch. Moralising Agents and Contexts”. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter, 2016., p. 173) rightly puts it, the sympotic works before Plato used to represent the symposium as a microcosm of a civilised society, its main themes being the right moral principles and patterns of ethical behaviour. After Plato, this kind of works tend to include philosophical discussions, because the symposium was a good example of how philosophical training could be achieved.

The best way to the introduce the QC is to refer to the contents of its own and inner introduction: the so-called proemium (612C-E). The main theme of this section is memory, namely if it is worth to remember what happened during a symposium. Plutarch begins his treatise commenting the popular saying 'I dislike a drinking-companion with a good memory' (612C1: ‘µισέω µνάµονα συµπόταν’)4 4 The author of this sentence is unknown. It probably was a popular saying. . His conclusion is that it is wise to forget all the foolish things (612D7: τῶν µὲν ἀτόπων ἡ λήθη τῷ ὄντι σοφή), but, as many philosophers before him did (he quotes Plato, Xenophon and many others), it is also useful to collect and register the 'learned discussions' they had during drinking (612E2-5: ἀναγράψασθαι λόγους παρὰ πότον γενοµένους ... φιλολογηθέντων συναγαγεῖν).

If we take Plutarch's words seriously, we should assume that these discussions really happened; some of them in Rome with his friend Sosius Senecius (to whom the QC are dedicated), others in Greece (612E3-4: πολλάκις ἔν τε Ῥώµῃ µεθ' ὑµῶν καὶ παρ' ἡµῖν ἐν τῇ ἑλλάδι). This is also relevant to the textual and literary status of the treatise. It is not a transcription of a specific symposium. It is instead a set of discussions that Plutarch himself collected from several symposia where he was drinking and talking with his friends. Yet, this does not mean that Plutarch's views overcome the opinions of the other participants nor that all his friends have similar views. As Brenk (2009_____. "'In Learned Conversation'. Plutarch’s Symposiac Literature and the Elusive Authorial Voice". In: FERREIRA, J. et al. (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 51-62., p. 51) puts it, 'His Symposiacs are a good example of lively discussions of different opinions among many speakers, often without necessarily indicating his own belief.'5 5 On this subject vide Ferrari (1995, pp. 30-31); Martín García (1987, pp. 12-14). I must say that I partially agree with Brenk, since in most cases Plutarch remains silent. But this is not true whenever key philosophical concepts or doctrines are being discussed. The best example is his full rejection of Epicureanism: even if his Epicurean friend Boetus is entitled to put forth is views, they are always refuted either by Plutarch himself or by his fellow platonists.

As such, the treatise contains an extremely wide variety of subjects thoroughly dissected through nine books of discussion. Plutarch’s intention in the QC was clearly to set forth a group of educated men discussing at the table under a model of conversation based on ethical criteria that would maintain the environment of mutual respect and politeness.6 6 Apud L. Van Der Stockt (2000, pp. 93-94). Therefore, the high cultural level of the participants offered the possibility to discuss, among many things, philosophical questions, problems and doctrines. It should be noted that the first πρόβληµα of this treatise is "If we should philosophize while drinking". Among Attic and Atticist writers, the incipit is normally about a key-theme, i.e. about a subject that has to do with the entire work. This clearly sets out the scope of the work not only on the centrality of philosophical discussions, but also on the necessity of different opinions to discuss.7 7 On these subjects, vide Xenophontos (2016, pp. 179-181). Not only as subject of discussion, but also as method to discuss, philosophy is present throughout the several symposia in a very diffuse way,8 8 On this subject see Kechagia (2011); Lopes (2009). placing the QC far closer from Plato and Xenophon’s works9 9 This affiliation is stated by Plutarch himself, when, in the Proemium, refers some philosophers that had composed sympotic works (612E; for further discussion vide Teodorsson, 1989-1996, ad loc; Vetta, 2000, p. 222). On the philosophical nature of the QC, see Klotz (2007, esp. pp. 650, 653); Romeri (2002, pp. 109-sqq.). than from the other kind of symposia defined by a spirit of amusement.10 10 The symposia directed to amusement and satire are those of Lucian of Samosata and of Athenaeus. On the relation between these sympotic works and Plutarch's vide Romeri (2002).

One of the many philosophical issues discussed at the table has to do with the origins and inner structure of the universe, i.e., cosmological discussions. It would be impossible to discuss in detail every passage of the QC that deals with cosmological issues. I chose to limit my analysis to the concepts of chance (τύχη), fate (εἱµαρµένη), ‘what depends on us’ (τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν), and providence (πρόνοια). Given the limitations of space, I will not provide a theoretical discussion of these concepts. Not even I intend to interpret them throughout Plutarch’s works.

Yet, the expression τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν, which I translate ‘what depends on us’, deserves further explanation. Many authors from Plutarchean scholarship translate it as ‘free-will’, but I find that quite problematic. It is well known the vexata quaestio on the ‘origins’ of the concept of free-will, namely the quarrel between Dihle, who says that the notion of will was invented by Augustine,11 11 Dihle (1982, p. 123: ‘the notion of will, as it is used as a tool of analysis and description in many philosophical doctrines from the early Scholastics to Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, was invented by St Augustine’). and Frede, to whom the concept of free-will emerges in Stoicism, namely with Epictetus.12 12 We may see this as a quarrel, because Frede’s book (2011) is intended to refute Dihle’s thesis (pp. 5-6 of the Introduction are quite explicit on that purpose). I find it really difficult to determine who invented a certain concept, and I have serious doubts that philosophical concepts can be ‘invented’. Besides, these ‘creationistic’ approaches seem to suffer from a problem of circularity, given that concepts such as ‘free-will’, or even ‘free’ or ‘will’, are not self-evident. Whenever one tries to point out the ‘invention’ of one of them, one is retroactively projecting his own preconception. In order to avoid problems of circularity and anachronism, I chose to translate the expression τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν in the most literal possible way and having in mind the context where it occurs for the first time. On this matter, Aristotle is our primary source. When discussing the ethical concept of 'choice' or 'deliberation' (προαίρεσις), at Ethica Nicomachea III.2, he says that 'choice seems to relate to the things that depend on us'.13 13 EN 1111b30: ἡ προαίρεσις περὶ τὰ ἐφ' ἡµῖν εἶναι. These 'things that depend on us' are τὰ ἐφ' ἡµῖν. Actually, a literal translation would be 'that on us', but it would sound uninteligible. Since the scope of προαίρεσις, according to Aristotle, is 'things that we believe to happen because of us',14 14 EN 1111b25-26: προαιρεῖται [...] ὅσα οἴεται γενέσθαι ἂν δι' αὑτοῦ. 'what depends on us' is a fair translation of τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν. For what it's worth, Aristotle also adds that προαίρεσις is something that we do voluntarily/willingly (ἑκούσιον).15 15 For further discussion vide Taylor (2006, ad loc). This could allow us to question the alleged absence of will or free-will before Augustine or the Stoics. But that would lead us to a discussion impossible to deal with, given the focus and limits of these pages.

2. Chance (τύχη)

Whenever this concept is introduced in the discussion to explain something, it is immediately refuted. This was absolutely expected, given Plutarch’s rejection of Epicurean doctrines.16 16 However, he does not seem to fully reject chance (τύχη). According to Brenk (1977, p. 154), Plutarch assigns a significant role to the concept when he is on strictly historical grounds; on the other hand, he criticizes it on philosophical grounds given its association with Epicureanism. Torraca (1996) argues that the concept of τύχη has a fundamental role together with φύσις in the De fortuna Romanorum (pp. 136-140) and with ἀρετή in De Alexandri magni fortuna aut virtute (pp. 147-149). On Plutarch's reading of Epicureanism vide Boulogne (1986) and Kechagia-Ovseiko (2014) for a general interpretation (in both cases, the conclusion is that Plutarch disagrees with the general principles of Epicureanism); Montiel (2010) for Plutarch's critique of Epicureanism as a form of atheism. When, during a discussion on the use of flowers during the symposium, it is argued that their only natural purpose is to produce visual and olfactory pleasure, it is not implied the Epicurean doctrine of ἡδονή as τέλος.17 17 See e.g. D.L. 10.128-129. According to Erato (a friend of Plutarch), flowers produce pleasure only because they were created with that particular purpose:

[...] ἕν γὰρ αὐτὸ δοκεῖ τοὐναντίον, εἰ µηδὲν ἡ φύσις, ὡς ὑµεῖς φατε, µάτην πεποίηκε, ταῦτα τῆς ἡδονῆς πεποιῆσθαι χάριν, ἃ µηδὲν ἄλλο χρήσιµον ἔχοντα µόνον εὐφραίνειν πέφυκεν. (646C3-5)

[...] for I think, on the contrary, that if nature has made nothing in vain (as you claim, I believe), it is for pleasure’s sake that she has made what by their nature only serve to delight us and possess no other useful quality.18 18 All translations of the QC are from the Loeb Classical Library with slight modifications.

Instead of being defined by chance, the structure of the natural world is pre-determined, each one of its elements having a specific role and purpose: everything functions the way it is supposed to function. Even the simplest attribute, like the fact that flowers are pleasant, has a reason to be just as it is. Later, on the third question of Book VIII, when the participants discuss the reason why sounds are clearer in the night, Ammonius, the first to speak, provides a similar explanation, saying that providence contrived accuracy to hearing to compensate for the limitations of vision (720D). Immediately Boetus (an Epicurean19 19 Boetus was one of Plutarch's oldest friends. He is known as 'the Epicureanist' throughout Plutarch's work, including the QC (e.g. Pyth. or. 5, 396 E; QC V 1,673 C). ) rejects this position and explains this strange physical mystery with a quotation of Epicurus: “what is moves in what is not”.20 20 720F3: Φέρεται τὰ ὄντ' ἐν τῷ µὴ ὄντι. Boetus’ quotation is the only testimonium for this Epicurean fragment. Usener (1887, fr. 323) accepts its authenticity, but neither Bailey (1926), Arrighetti (1960) nor Long & Sedley (1987) include it in their editions. Alluding to the atomistic axiom according to which “what is” (τὸ ὃν) corresponds to the completeness of matter (τὸ πλήρες) and “what is not” (τὸ µὴ ὃν) is “the void” (τὸ κένον),21 21 Cf. e.g. DK67A6 / LM27 D31, R38 = Arist. Metaph. 985b4-sqq.; DK68A37 / LM27 D29 = Simp. in Cael. VII.294.33-sqq.; Lucr. I.420-421. Boetus argues that during the night atoms are extremely compressed and there is more unoccupied space through which the sounds travel (720F-721D). Plutarch himself fiercely objects to this analysis, claiming that sounds result from striking of bodies in the air - a position also held by Plato22 22 See Ti. 67b. On Plutarch's reading of Platonism vide Dillon (1996; 2014); Jones (1916). and Aristotle23 23 See de An. 419b4-420a2. On the peripatetic trends and themes throughout the QC vide Oikonomopoulou (2011). On Plutarch's reading of Aristotle and the Peripatetic tradition vide Babut (1996); Becchi (2014). -, but the discussion only reaches an end with a further refutation added by Thrasyllus (son of Ammonius). He says that it is an error to search for causes other than Zeus himself (722D).

A superficial reading of these passages may suggest a Stoic understanding of the sensible world24 24 On Plutarch's views of Stoicism vide Babut (1969); Hershbell (1992); Opsomer (2014). . The apparently determinist description of the purpose of flowers, the use of the term npóvoia in Ammonius’ speech, or even Zeus as a ruler of the universe25 25 The Stoic association of Zeus with the goverment of the universe is noticed by Plutarch in De Stoic. rep. 1056B (= SVF II.997). summon the concept of fate as cosmological principle. However, a closer look will prevent that interpretation.

In the first passage, it is suggested that the natural processes are determined to occur, but it is also clear the idea that they obey a higher principle. When Erato says that “nature has made nothing in vain” (646C4-5: µηδὲν ἡ φύσις [...] µάτην πεποίηκε), he’s quoting, almost ipsis verbis, a passage from Aristotle’s De Anima: “nature does nothing in vain, for everything by nature is for the sake of something” (434a31-32: µηθὲν µάτην ποιεῖ ἡ φύσις. ἕνεκά του γὰρ πάντα ὑπάρχει τὰ φύσει).26 26 Aristotle states this principle also in Cael. 290a31, GA 744a36-37, Ph. 197b22-29. Thus, besides rejecting that phenomena happen in vain (µάτην), this intertextual connection highlights an affiliation with the Aristotelian theory of natural teleology that surpasses the Stoic conception of pure necessity and inevitability. All things happen not only because they are meant to happen, but also - and mainly, I would add - due to the sake of the best purpose.27 27 See Arist. EN 1099b-21-22; GA 738a37-b1; PA 645a-23-25. On Aristotelian natural teleology see further in Johnson (2005, pp. 80-82); Broadie (2007, pp. 85-100).

These principles also apply to the animal realm, including humans, considering not only the way they interact with nature, but also their inner structure. In a πρόβληµα on human anatomy, in which it is discussed whether drink passes through the lung or not, Plutarch himself concludes with the following explanation:

[...] ὅσοις πλεύµων οὐκ ἐµπέφυκε τῶν ζῴων ἢ σφόδρα µικρὸς ἐµπέφυκε, ταῦτ' οὐ δεῖται ποτοῦ τὸ παράπαν οὐδ' ὀρέγεται, διὰ τὸ τῶν µορίων ἑκάστῳ σύµφυτον ὑπάρχειν τὴν πρὸς τοὔργον ἐπιθυµίαν, οἷς δ' οὐκ ἔστι µόρια, µηδὲ χρείαν παρεῖναι µηδὲ προθυµίαν τῆς δι' αὐτῶν ἐνεργείας. (699E6-F1)

[...] the creatures to whom nature has not given a lung, or has given only a very small one, do not need to drink at all, and feel no desire for it, because a natural concomitant of each organ is the desire directed toward fulfilment of its function, and creatures that do not have certain parts have neither a need for them nor any eagerness for the activity that employs them.

This exposition requires a further explanation. The title of this πρόβληµα is “Against those who censured Plato for having said that drinking passes through the lung”. The Platonic passage at stake is Timaeus 70c-d, but the participants never refer to the dialogue. After a wide discussion on the subject, which was full of quotations from several Greek poets and philosophers, Plutarch interrupts with a fierce “enough of witnesses!” (699D9-10: µαρτύρων µὲν οὖν ἅλις) and provides the final explanation. It is one of the few moments throughout the QC where the author Plutarch extends its authority to his corresponding character.

His explanation also depends on several passages of the Timaeus which he neither quotes nor refers to. First of all, he's assuming one general principle which was established in the beginning of the dialogue: the world was created without hands or feet since it would not need to walk nor grab something (33d). He seems also taking in account the last pages of the dialogue (90e-sqq.), where Timaeus describes the elements and organs that each animal species receives according to their biological needs. The same principle applies inversely: they will only have need of things that can be received by one of their inborn organs. According to the general principle stated at 33b, the structure of the natural elements must correspond exactly to their congenital functions - no more, no less. Plutarch's final explanation to this πρόβληµα depends entirely on these passages of the Timaeus, even if he never refers to the dialogue.

3. Fate (εἱµαρµένη) and ‘what depends on us’ (τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν)

In the ninth πρόβληµα of Book VIII, the participants debate if it is possible to consider the generation of new diseases. Most of them believed that this was not possible, claiming that nature is not a “lover of novelty” (731B7: φιλόκαινον) nor a “producer of new things” (731B7-8: νέων πραγµάτων δηµιουργὸν), but the discussion goes on anyway. The first speaker argues that the only way to accept the generation of new diseases was to admit the introduction of elements (such as a new kind of air or a strange type of water) from other worlds or 'interworlds' (731D8-9: ἐξ ἑτέρων τινῶν κόσµων ἢ µετακοσµίων). After a long discussion, this atomistic proposition28 28 The existence of other worlds was initially proposed by Leucippus (DK67A24 / LM27R86 = Aët. 1.4.1-sqq.; D.L. 10.88-sqq.) and Democritus (DK68A40 / LM27 P7, P18, D81, D92 = Hippol. Haer. 1.13) and adopted by Epicureanism (Epicur. Ep. Hdt. 45 = D.L. 10.45). is promptly criticized by Plutarch himself, who does not accept the existence of an infinite number of worlds, because indetermination and undefinition are adverse to the natural order of the universe (732E8: τὸ παρὰ τὴν φύσιν εὐθὺς ἀόριστον καὶ ἄπειρόν ἐστιν).29 29 In De def. orac. 423C, the infinity of worlds is criticized on the ground that it would lead to the supremacy of chance (TÚxn) in the universe. See further in Dillon (1996, pp. 224-225). However, the fact that the world is ordered does not imply that all the combinations between its elements are pre-determined and that it is not possible to generate new ones. Plutarch rather thinks that the multiple mixing of so many properties in different degrees may generate new diseases; he gives the example of food and drink as a source of variations in different qualities and arrangements (733A-B). The 'gastronomic' exemplum is reinforced with a logic counterpart: according to Chrysippus, the number of compound propositions that can be made from only ten simple propositions exceeds a million;30 30 732F5-7: καὶ Χρύσιππος τὰς ἐκ δέκα µόνων ἀξιωµάτων συµπλοκὰς πλήθει φησὶν ἑκατὸν µυριάδας ὑπερβάλλειν· This very same wording is repeated at De stoicorum repugantiis 1047C. These texts are the only sources for Chrysippus’ frg. 210 (vide SVF II.210, p. 69). according to Xenocrates, the number of syllables which the letters will make in combination is 1.002.000.000.000.31 31 Ξενοκράτης δὲ τὸν τῶν συλλαβῶν ἀριθµόν, ὃν τὰ στοιχεῖα µιγνύµενα πρὸς ἄλληλα παρέχει, µυριάδων ἀπέφηνεν εἰκοσάκις καὶ µυριάκις µυρίων. This is Xenophanes’ frg. 11 according to the edition by Heinze (1892). This means that men have the ability to recreate some natural processes, since they are free to combine some elements and generate new things that will affect them. This entails a margin of human agency in the natural realm: even if men cannot create new substances, they can produce new things through the combination of pre-existing elements.

There is another passage in the QC (740B-D) that focuses the preponderance of human agency. The title of the πρόβληµα (the fifth of Book IX) is 'Why did Plato say that the soul of Ajax came twentieth to the drawing of lots?'. The subtext is, evidently, the so-called Myth of Er with which Plato concludes the Republic; and surely one of his locus classicus to discuss human responsibility. After a jesting initial discussion, Lamprias (Plutarch's brother) provides an explanation of the casting of lots by the souls that a modern Platonist will find extremely awkward, since it implies an allegedly platonic theory of three causes (740C): fate (sípappévq), chance (rú%q) and “what depends on us” (τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν):

ἀεὶ µὲν γὰρ ἅπτεται τῶν τριῶν αἰτιῶν, ἅτε δὴ πρῶτος ἢ µάλιστα συνιδών, ὅπη τὸ καθ' εἱµαρµένην τῷ κατὰ τύχην αὖθίς τε τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν ἑκατέρῳ καὶ συναµφοτέροις ἐπιµίγνυσθαι καὶ συµπλέκεσθαι πέφυκε. (740C6-10)

He [Plato] always makes use of three causes, for was him who first or best perceived how, by nature, what has to do with fate mingles and interweaves with what has to do with chance, and what depends on us with each of those singly or with both simultaneously.

Allegedly platonic, because Plato did not postulate it, at least, not intentionally. The only passage from the Dialogues in which one can find a tripartite model of causality would be Laws 768b-c, where the Athenian Stranger says that the only things32 32 I use 'things', because in Plato's text there is no word or expression like αἴτιον, αἰτία, διὰ + accusative or causal dative, or any other that Plato uses to express the idea of cause (vide Sedley, 1998, pp. 114-116). that direct human affairs (τἀνθρώπινα διακυβερνῶσι) are a god (θεός), chance and opportunity together with the god (µετὰ θεοῦ τύχη καὶ καιρός), or all of these combined with a technique or skill (συγχωρῆσαι τούτοις δεῖν ἕπεσθαι τέχνην). Even if it is tempting to point at this passage as the source of Lamprias' explanation, the only elements that both texts have in common is the use of a tripartite model to explain causality and the idea that causes tend to act simultaneously. One also may relate Plato's τύχη καὶ καιρός with Plutarch's rú%q, but that cannot be extended to the other elements. Not only θεός and τὸ καθ' εἱµαρµένην are completely different things, but also Plato could have used ἡ εἱµαρµένη (e.g. Phd. 115a; Grg. 512e) instead of θεός and Plutarch could have used θεός instead of τὸ καθ' εἱµαρµένην. As for the identification of Plato's τέχνη with Plutarch's τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν, it would also be exaggerated: not only the expression τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν can refer to a wide variety of phenomena (specially ethical ones) that are not comprised by τέχνη, but it also occurs for the first time in Aristotle. That is probably why some authors suggest33 33 Vide Dillon (1996, p. 209); Teodorsson (1989-1996, ad loc). a line from Ethica Nicomachea as source of this passage:

αἰτίαι γὰρ δοκοῦσιν εἶναι φύσις καὶ ἀνάγκη καὶ τύχη, ἔτι δὲ νοῦς καὶ πᾶν τὸ δι' ἀνθρώπου. (1112a32-33)

Nature, necessity, and chance are thought to be causes, and also intellect and everything that depends on man.

This hypothesis is more interesting from a terminological standpoint, since ἀνάγκη can easily be identified with τὸ καθ' εἱµαρµένην, and νοῦς καὶ πᾶν τὸ δι' ἀνθρώπου may correspond to τὸ ἐφ' ἡµῖν; besides the repetition of τύχη and the specification that these elements are αἰτίαι. Yet, Aristotle (as usual) uses a quadripartite model, not a tripartite one. Besides, the discussion is on a specific passage of Plato's Republic and the participants never quote nor refer to Aristotle. A plausible answer would be that perhaps Plutarch has in mind both texts (Laws 768b-c and EN 1112a32-33). Not only the authors of Late Antiquity, unlike modern scholars, did not see Plato and Aristotle as antagonists, but it also was normal to use ancient sources without explicit citation.

Leaving aside these difficulties, let’s get back to Lamprias’ interpretation of the Platonic text. The previous passages allow us to assume that (1) none of these causes acts by itself, i.e. without being mingled with other cause; (2) fate and chance always act simultaneously; (3) what depends on us is always mingled with chance, fate or both. But in the subsequent lines, Lamprias suggests that fate is somehow submitted to ‘what depends on us’, saying that the “good life of those who choose correctly” (740D3: τὸ δ' εὖ βιοῦν τοὺς ὀρθῶς ἑλοµένους) is connected/bound (740D4: συνάπτων) with the “necessity of fate” (740D4: εἱµαρµένης ἀνάγκῃ). If fate determines a good or a bad life depending on a previous conduct defined by our personal choices,34 34 Brenk (1977, p. 155) also shares this opinion. what exactly is fate? In the end, if it is pre-determined by an earlier kind of independent ‘what depends on us’, fate is nothing but the final sum of our intentional decisions.35 35 There is a similar definition of sipappsvq in De Fato (570) that also includes providence. The problem is that this work is considered apocryphal. See further details in Froidefond (1987, p. 226). As for chance, the problem is similar: first, Lamprias identifies it with external factors, like the educational and political background we live in, that do not depend on us, but are determined by a casual casting of lots (740D5: τῶν κλήρων ἀτάκτως διασπειροµένων). But right after, he adds that the casting of lots does not happen by chance (740D10: οὐκέτι γίνεται κατὰ τύχην), but from a sort of fate and providence (740D10-11: ἀλλ' ἔκ τινος εἱµαρµένης καὶ προνοίας). Thus, if fate is the sum of our intentional actions, and, at the same time, determines the casting of lots, fate and chance are nothing but a consequence of ‘what depends on us’ and not its cause. However, this interpretation only makes sense if we have in mind the context of the platonic hypotext, meaning that the three causes only apply to a circular conception of life. That inevitable connection is quite evident for two reasons. First, Lamprias is always speaking for Plato.36 36 It is worth noting that the verbs of his speech are either participles or forms of the third person. Second, Plato’s text suggests the very same idea: “responsibility is on the one who chooses” (R. 617e4: αἰτία ἑλοµένου).

As we have seen, Lamprias’ speech also includes the concept of providence, but it does not give further notice on its implications. We notice that, together with fate, it determines the casting of the lots, but, on the other hand, it is not included in the group of the three causes. For that reason, it is tempting to merge it with fate, claiming a Stoic influence in this passage.37 37 Plutarch himself noticed the Stoic tendency to merge εἱµαρµένη and πρόνοια in De Stoic. rep. 1050A-B (= SVF II. 937). At the same time, it is equally dangerous, given the critiques that Plutarch directs towards Stoic providence for the determinism it entails.38 38 On this subject vide Opsomer (2014, pp. 91-93).

That brings us back to a previous question: what does Plutarch means by npóvoia in the QC? And it also adds a new one: how does providence deals with that notion of ‘what depends on us’?

4. Providence (npóvoia)

In the first πρόβληµα of Book VIII, the Platonist Tyndares says that, according to Plato, the father and creator of the universe (718A3: πατέρα καὶ ποιητὴν τοῦ τε κόσµου) is the ungenerated and eternal God39 39 I chose to write ‘God’ with a capital ‘G’ because Plutarch’s religious doctrine is substantially monotheistic. Even if he assumes the existence of many divine entities, he recognizes the existence of a supreme God. On this subject vide Hirsch-Luipold (2014, pp. 166-170), who suggests the label ‘polylatric monotheism’ for Plutarch’s views on religion. (718A4: τὸν ἀγέννητον καὶ ἀίδιον θεὸν). Tyndares is obviously alluding to the demiurge of the Timaeus (28c3-4: ποιητὴν καὶ πατέρα τοῦδε τοῦ παντός), but he adds two elements, when he says that this God is ungenerated and eternal. In Plato’s text, only the Forms are ungenerated (52a1: ἀγέννητον) and eternal (29a3: ἀίδιον). As we will see, this conceptual fusion is not innocent.40 40 This vocabular link is also in the De E (e.g. 373A5-6, 382F5-383A4). However, this does not entail that Plutarch considered Ideas as “the thoughts of God”; see further discussion in Ferrari (1995, pp. 242-247); Froidefond (1987, pp. 225-227).

On the other hand, even if the qualities of father and creator are expressly applied to the demiurge in the Timaeus, we know from other works that Plutarch held a very original interpretation which entails different conclusions. In the Platonicae quaestiones he dedicates the second ζήτηµα to this issue, arguing that the demiurge is father of men and creator of the universe41 41 This polemical interpretation is rejected by Proclus (in Tim. 1.319.15-16). For a thorough analysis of this ζήτηµα, see Ferrari (1996, pp. 395-409). . This distinction may imply that, after having created the universe, the demiurge kept governing his work. But since, according to the Timaeus, the demiurge retires after the creation process and assigns the government of the universe to the cosmic soul, Plutarch’s interpretation requires further clarification.

The reference to the demiurge introduces a new πρόβληµα (718C-ff), the second one of Book VIII, whose title is “In what sense does Plato say that God is always using geometry?”. In fact, Plato did not say anything like that in any of the dialogues.42 42 This authorial problem is raised by Diogenianus in the first lines of the πρόβληµα. Plutarch himself admits it (718C), but he also adds that this statement is tuned in with Plato’s convictions. By validating this initial premise, Plutarch directs the discussion towards that previous interpretation of the demiurge as creator of the universe and father of men: not only the God used geometry in the creation process, but he also keeps using it (718C3: ἀεί) - while he rules the universe, we might add.

After this brief narratological digression, the discussion begins. First, Tyndares talks about the importance and range of geometry, and then Florus invokes a comparison between mathematics and politics theorized by Plato43 43 See Grg. 508a; Lg. 757b-c; R. 558c. and materialized by Lycurgus. According to Florus, the Spartan statesman had banished from Lacedaemon the arithmetical proportion (akin to democracy), because it distributes an equal amount according to a number, and introduced the geometric one (akin to oligarchy) for the reason that it considers the worth (metaphorically, the geometric form) besides number (719A-C). Leaving aside the historical implications of this passage, we may just say that arithmetical proportion creates disorder and chaos because it only takes in account the numbers. On the contrary, geometry produces order by distributing different amounts according to fixed criteria.

After this polemical statement, Autobulus is called upon to refute it. He declines the invitation, perhaps because he also believes that geometry generates order from disorder, and provides his own interpretation of the demiurgic creation:

ἔφη γὰρ οὔτε τὴν γεωµετρίαν ἄλλου τινὸς ἢ τῶν περὶ τὰ πέρατα συµπτωµάτων καὶ παθῶν εἶναι θεωρητικήν, οὔτε τὸν θεὸν ἑτέρῳ τινὶ τρόπῳ κοσµοποιεῖν ἢ περατοῦντα τὴν ὕλην ἄπειρον οὖσαν [...]. (719C7-10)

[the narrator speaking] He [Autobulus] said that geometry has no other subject than the properties and characteristics of limits, and that God, when creating the universe, uses no other method than that of imposing limitation on matter, which is unlimited [...].

Throughout his speech, Autobulus will describe the process in detail, insisting in the assignment of the geometric forms to the four basic elements, so that everything may begin from a rational point.44 44 Cf. Pl. Ti. 53c-56b. But the main idea is that through geometry God imposes limits on a pre-cosmic irrational matter and establishes an order: he creates a κόσµος.45 45 On Plutarch’s use of the platonic doctrine of the mathematical rationalization of the cosmos see Ferrari (1995, pp. 117-147).

Finally, it is Plutarch himself who concludes the discussion. He recovers his initial thesis of the demiurge as creator and father and frames it in the cosmological context that had just been outlined through the entire πρόβληµα:

ἀεὶ γὰρ ὢν διὰ τὴν σύµφυτον ἀνάγκην τοῦ σώµατος ἐν γενέσει καὶ µετατροπῇ καὶ πάθεσι παντοδαποῖς ὑπὸ τοῦ πατρὸς καὶ δηµιουργοῦ βοηθεῖται τῷ λόγῳ πρὸς τὸ παράδειγµα τὴν οὐσίαν ὁρίζοντος· ᾗ καὶ κάλλιον τοῦ συµµέτρου τὸ περὶ µέτρον τῶν ὄντων. (720B10-C4)

Being continuously involved in becoming and shifting and all kinds of events, because of its congenital with its body, the universe is assisted by the Father and Creator, who, by means of reason, and with reference to the model, gives limits to that which exists. Thus, the aspect of measure in things is even more beautiful than their symmetry.

Since the sensible world is in constant change, the demiurge must assure its conformity to the model - the Forms, of course. However, this seems to entail that the creator must be somehow present in the world, so that he may maintain it in accordance with the archetype.

Again, the connection with Stoicism is tempting, given the idea of the presence of God in nature. But we know that Plutarch did not accept the Stoic doctrine of immanentism, on the grounds that God must be absolutely transcendent and cannot have neither corporeal nor material essence;46 46 Plutarch refers this conception of God in the De Iside 373A, 377E-F, 382F-383A. See further in Hershbell (1992, p. 3348); Karamanolis (2006, p. 109); Babut (1969, pp. 453-465); Cacciatore (2009, p. 290). that is why the τέλος of human life should be likeness to God (ὁµοίωσις τῷ θεῷ), rather than conformity to Nature, like it was to Stoics.47 47 Vide Dillon (1996, pp. 192-193). For a thorough analysis on Plutarch’s ὁµοίωσις τῷ θεῷ, see Becchi (1996). But how can it be possible that God is present in the world and, at the same time, to be transcendent?

The answer is outlined in Tyndares’ speech. First, he says that through the mathematical sciences we see “traces and ghost-images of the intelligibles’ truth” (718E3-4: τῆς τῶν νοητῶν ἀληθείας ἴχνη καὶ εἴδωλα), implying that the Forms are indirectly in the geometrical figures.48 48 See further details in Ferrari (1995, pp. 156-158; 2009, p. 90). Besides that, he mentions that geometry must be used by men to contemplate the “eternal and immaterial images in the presence of which God is always God” (718F3-4: τῶν ἀιδίων καὶ ἀσωµάτων εἰκόνων, πρὸς αἷσπερ ὢν ὁ θεὸς ἀεὶ θεός ἐστιν; cf. Pl. Phdr. 249c.), suggesting that God is in the Forms, as will be said in the Platonicae quaestiones: “God is in the intelligibles” (1002B10: ὁ γάρ θεὸς ἐν τοῖς νοητοῖς; cf. Ferrari, 2009FERRARI, F. “Simposio e Filosofia: il Problema del «Dio Geometra»”. In: FERREIRA, J. et al. (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 87-96., p. 91). Thus, if we know that God created the world by contemplating the Forms, we may suppose that He is in the world through the Forms.

5. Possible conclusions

The cosmological insight that Plutarch outlines in the QC is perfectly tuned in with his philosophical curriculum. As a Platonist, he fully rejects the interference of chance in the world’s formation and inner structure, and also denotes a profound distrust in Stoic doctrines of fate and providence for being (in his view) excessively deterministic. The alternative is a teleological model, which, as we have seen, combines elements from both Plato and Aristotle.

We should note, however, that Plutarch's reading is selective. From the Timaeus, he argues that the universe is a rationally conceived livingbeing, which is indirectly administrated by a single divine entity - a form of transcendent providence present in the sensible world through the dependence to an archetypical model. But we know that in Plato's dialogue this permanent operation is maintained by the cosmic soul, not by the demiurge. From Aristotle's natural teleology, he argues that each being has its purpose, because nature does not produce things in vain. This also entails that the whole cosmos has a purpose, which was imprinted by the time of its creation. But we also know that, according to Aristotle, the world was not created.

As usual among Platonists, cosmology is not relegated to a scientific investigation. The explanation of natural processes and their origins have to deal with human agency beyond biology and physics. The ethical counterpart of this cosmological doctrine has to do mostly with responsibility. On this matter, Plutarch also uses elements from both Plato and Aristotle. The interpretation of the Myth of Er shows that, even if fate and chance are always included in human affairs, their interference depends on the choice that souls decided to do before entering the body. The most probable influence of Ethica Nicomachea III.2, at least on vocabulary grounds, allowed Plutarch to add the element 'what depends on us' to reinforce the idea that our fate is determined by our choices; not only our day-to-day decisions, but mainly the kind of live that, according do Platonic theology, we choose willingly.

Acronyms49 49 For Greek authors, I followed the Liddell & Scott's Greek-English Lexicon abbreviations. For Latin authors, I followed the Glare's Oxford Latin Dictionary abbreviations.

DK = DIELS, H. & KRANZ, W. (1952DIELS, H. & KRANZ, W. “Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker”. 3 Vols. 6th. ed. repr. 2005. Zürich: Weidmann, 1952.).

LM = LAKS, A. & MOST, G. (2016LAKS, A., MOST, G. “Early Greek Philosophy”. Cambridge Mass./London: Harvard University Press, 9 Vols., 2016.).

SVF = VON ARNIM, H. (1903-1905)VON ARNIM, H. “Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta”. Stutgardia: Bibliotheca Teubneriana, 1903-1905..

  • 1
    Pages 612-748 (the whole vol. VIII) in the Stephanus edition. From now on, the Quaestiones convivales will be referred as QC. For a global analysis and bibliography on this treatise vide Ferreira et al. (2009)FERREIRA, J. et al. (eds.). “Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch”. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009.; Klotz & Oikonomopoulou (2011)KLOTZ, F., OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. (eds.). “The Philosopher’s Banquet. Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011..
  • 2
    For a general view on the symposion as a social institution vide Murray (1990)MURRAY, O. “Sympotica. A Symposium on the Symposion”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.; Orfanos & Carrière (2003)ORFANOS, C., CARRIÈRE, J. “Symposium: banquet et représentations en Grèce et à Rome”. Toulouse: Université de Toulouse, 2003.; Hobden (2013)HOBDEN, F. “The Symposion in Ancient Greek Society and Thought”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013..
  • 3
    On sympotic works before Plato vide Bowie (1993)BOWIE, E. "Greek Table-talk before Plato". Rhetorica, 11, pp. 355-71, 1993.; and Romeri (2002)ROMERI, L. “Philosophes entre Mots et Mets. Plutarque, Lucien et Athénée autour de la Table de Platon”. Grenoble: Jérôme Millón, 2002. on works after Plato.
  • 4
    The author of this sentence is unknown. It probably was a popular saying.
  • 5
    On this subject vide Ferrari (1995_____. “Dio, Idee e Materia. La Struttura del Cosmo in Plutarco di Cheronea.” Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1995., pp. 30-31); Martín García (1987MARTÍN GARCÍA, F. “Plutarco. Obras Morales y de Costumbres (Moralia) IV (Charlas de Sobremesa)”. Madrid: Gredos, 1987., pp. 12-14).
  • 6
    Apud L. Van Der Stockt (2000VAN DER STOCKT, L. “Aspects of the Ethics and poetics of the Dialogue in the Corpus Plularcheum". In: GALLO, I., MORESCHINI, C. (eds.). I Generi Letterari in Plutarco. Atti del VIII Convegno Plutarcheo, Pisa, 2-4 giugno 1999. Napoli: M. D'Aura 2000. PP. 93-50., pp. 93-94).
  • 7
    On these subjects, vide Xenophontos (2016, pp. 179-181).
  • 8
    On this subject see Kechagia (2011)KECHAGIA, E. "Philosophy in Plutarch’s Table Talk. In Jest or in Earnest?". In: KLOTZ, F., OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. (eds.). The Philosopher S Banquet. Plutarch S Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. pp. 77-104.; Lopes (2009)LOPES, R. “The Omnipresence of Philosophy in Plutarch’s Quaestiones Convivales". In: FERREIRA, J. et al. (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 415-424..
  • 9
    This affiliation is stated by Plutarch himself, when, in the Proemium, refers some philosophers that had composed sympotic works (612E; for further discussion vide Teodorsson, 1989-1996TEODORSSON, S.-T. “A Commentary on Plutarch’s Table Talks”. Goteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis, 1989-1996., ad loc; Vetta, 2000VAN DER STOCKT, L. “Aspects of the Ethics and poetics of the Dialogue in the Corpus Plularcheum". In: GALLO, I., MORESCHINI, C. (eds.). I Generi Letterari in Plutarco. Atti del VIII Convegno Plutarcheo, Pisa, 2-4 giugno 1999. Napoli: M. D'Aura 2000. PP. 93-50., p. 222). On the philosophical nature of the QC, see Klotz (2007KLOTZ, F. “Portraits of the Philosopher: Plutarch’s Self-Presentation in the Quaestiones convivales” CQ, 57.2, pp. 650-667, 2007., esp. pp. 650, 653); Romeri (2002ROMERI, L. “Philosophes entre Mots et Mets. Plutarque, Lucien et Athénée autour de la Table de Platon”. Grenoble: Jérôme Millón, 2002., pp. 109-sqq.).
  • 10
    The symposia directed to amusement and satire are those of Lucian of Samosata and of Athenaeus. On the relation between these sympotic works and Plutarch's vide Romeri (2002)ROMERI, L. “Philosophes entre Mots et Mets. Plutarque, Lucien et Athénée autour de la Table de Platon”. Grenoble: Jérôme Millón, 2002..
  • 11
    Dihle (1982DIHLE, A. “The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity”. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982., p. 123: ‘the notion of will, as it is used as a tool of analysis and description in many philosophical doctrines from the early Scholastics to Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, was invented by St Augustine’).
  • 12
    We may see this as a quarrel, because Frede’s book (2011)FREDE, M. “A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought”. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011. is intended to refute Dihle’s thesis (pp. 5-6 of the Introduction are quite explicit on that purpose).
  • 13
    EN 1111b30: ἡ προαίρεσις περὶ τὰ ἐφ' ἡµῖν εἶναι.
  • 14
    EN 1111b25-26: προαιρεῖται [...] ὅσα οἴεται γενέσθαι ἂν δι' αὑτοῦ.
  • 15
    For further discussion vide Taylor (2006TAYLOR, C. “Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics”. Books II-IV. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006., ad loc).
  • 16
    However, he does not seem to fully reject chance (τύχη). According to Brenk (1977BRENK, F. “In Mist Apparelled. Religious Themes in Plutarch’s Moralia and Lives'”. Leiden: Brill, 1977., p. 154), Plutarch assigns a significant role to the concept when he is on strictly historical grounds; on the other hand, he criticizes it on philosophical grounds given its association with Epicureanism. Torraca (1996)TORRACA, L. “I Presupositi della Tyche Plutarchea”. In: GALLO, I. (ed.). Plutarco e la Religione. Atti del VI Convegno Plutarcheo (Ravello, 29-31 maggio 1995). Napoli: M. DAuria, 1996. pp. 105-155. argues that the concept of τύχη has a fundamental role together with φύσις in the De fortuna Romanorum (pp. 136-140) and with ἀρετή in De Alexandri magni fortuna aut virtute (pp. 147-149). On Plutarch's reading of Epicureanism vide Boulogne (1986)BOULOGNE, J. “Plutarque et l’épicurisme”. Paris: Doctorat soutenue à Paris 4, 1986. and Kechagia-Ovseiko (2014)KECHAGIA-OVSEIKO, E. (2011). "Plutarch and Epicureanism". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch. Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 104-120. for a general interpretation (in both cases, the conclusion is that Plutarch disagrees with the general principles of Epicureanism); Montiel (2010)MONTIEL, J. "Superstición y ateísmo en la crítica antiepicúrea de Plutarco". In: LEÃO, D., FRAZIER, F. (eds.). Tychè et Pronoia - La marche du monde selon Plutarque. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2010. pp. 57-68. for Plutarch's critique of Epicureanism as a form of atheism.
  • 17
    See e.g. D.L. 10.128-129.
  • 18
    All translations of the QC are from the Loeb Classical Library with slight modifications.
  • 19
    Boetus was one of Plutarch's oldest friends. He is known as 'the Epicureanist' throughout Plutarch's work, including the QC (e.g. Pyth. or. 5, 396 E; QC V 1,673 C).
  • 20
    720F3: Φέρεται τὰ ὄντ' ἐν τῷ µὴ ὄντι. Boetus’ quotation is the only testimonium for this Epicurean fragment. Usener (1887USENER, H. Epicúrea. Lipsiae: [s.e.], 1887., fr. 323) accepts its authenticity, but neither Bailey (1926)BAILEY, C. “Epicurus: the Extant Remains”. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1926., Arrighetti (1960)ARRIGHETTI, G. “Epicuro: Opere”. Torino: Einaudi, 1960. nor Long & Sedley (1987)LONG, A., SEDLEY, D. “The Hellenistic Philosophers”. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 2 Vols., 1987. include it in their editions.
  • 21
    Cf. e.g. DK67A6 / LM27 D31, R38 = Arist. Metaph. 985b4-sqq.; DK68A37 / LM27 D29 = Simp. in Cael. VII.294.33-sqq.; Lucr. I.420-421.
  • 22
    See Ti. 67b. On Plutarch's reading of Platonism vide Dillon (1996DILLON, J. “The Middle Platonists. 80 B.C to A.D. 220”. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996.; 2014_____. "Plutarch and Platonism". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch. Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 61-72.); Jones (1916)JONES, R. “The Platonism of Plutarch”. Menasha: George Banta Publishing Company, 1916..
  • 23
    See de An. 419b4-420a2. On the peripatetic trends and themes throughout the QC vide Oikonomopoulou (2011)OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. "Peripatetic Knowledge in Plutarch’s Table Talk". In: KLOTZ, F., OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. (eds.). The Philosopher’s Banquet. Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. pp. 105-130.. On Plutarch's reading of Aristotle and the Peripatetic tradition vide Babut (1996)_____. "Plutarque, Aristote, et l’ Aristotélisme". In: VAN DER STOCKT, L. (ed.). Plutarchea Lovaniensia: a Miscellany of Essays on Plutarch. Louvain: Université Catholique de Louvain, 1996. pp. 1-28.; Becchi (2014)_____. "Plutarch, Aristotle, and the Peripatetics". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch. Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 73-87..
  • 24
    On Plutarch's views of Stoicism vide Babut (1969)BABUT, D. “Plutarque et le Stoïcisme”. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1969.; Hershbell (1992)HERSHBELL, J. “Plutarch and Stoicism”. ANRW, II.36, pp. 3336-3352, 1992.; Opsomer (2014)OPSOMER, J. "Plutarch and the Stoics". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch. Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 88-103..
  • 25
    The Stoic association of Zeus with the goverment of the universe is noticed by Plutarch in De Stoic. rep. 1056B (= SVF II.997).
  • 26
    Aristotle states this principle also in Cael. 290a31, GA 744a36-37, Ph. 197b22-29.
  • 27
    See Arist. EN 1099b-21-22; GA 738a37-b1; PA 645a-23-25. On Aristotelian natural teleology see further in Johnson (2005JOHNSON, M. “Aristotle on Teleology”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005., pp. 80-82); Broadie (2007BROADIE, S. “Aristotle and Beyond. Essays on Metaphysics and Ethics”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007., pp. 85-100).
  • 28
    The existence of other worlds was initially proposed by Leucippus (DK67A24 / LM27R86 = Aët. 1.4.1-sqq.; D.L. 10.88-sqq.) and Democritus (DK68A40 / LM27 P7, P18, D81, D92 = Hippol. Haer. 1.13) and adopted by Epicureanism (Epicur. Ep. Hdt. 45 = D.L. 10.45).
  • 29
    In De def. orac. 423C, the infinity of worlds is criticized on the ground that it would lead to the supremacy of chance (TÚxn) in the universe. See further in Dillon (1996DILLON, J. “The Middle Platonists. 80 B.C to A.D. 220”. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996., pp. 224-225).
  • 30
    732F5-7: καὶ Χρύσιππος τὰς ἐκ δέκα µόνων ἀξιωµάτων συµπλοκὰς πλήθει φησὶν ἑκατὸν µυριάδας ὑπερβάλλειν· This very same wording is repeated at De stoicorum repugantiis 1047C. These texts are the only sources for Chrysippus’ frg. 210 (vide SVF II.210, p. 69).
  • 31
    Ξενοκράτης δὲ τὸν τῶν συλλαβῶν ἀριθµόν, ὃν τὰ στοιχεῖα µιγνύµενα πρὸς ἄλληλα παρέχει, µυριάδων ἀπέφηνεν εἰκοσάκις καὶ µυριάκις µυρίων. This is Xenophanes’ frg. 11 according to the edition by Heinze (1892)HEINZE, R. “Xenocrates”. Stuttgart: Teubner, 1892..
  • 32
    I use 'things', because in Plato's text there is no word or expression like αἴτιον, αἰτία, διὰ + accusative or causal dative, or any other that Plato uses to express the idea of cause (vide Sedley, 1998SEDLEY, D. "Platonic Causes". Phronesis, XLIII/2, pp. 114-132, 1998., pp. 114-116).
  • 33
    Vide Dillon (1996DILLON, J. “The Middle Platonists. 80 B.C to A.D. 220”. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996., p. 209); Teodorsson (1989-1996TEODORSSON, S.-T. “A Commentary on Plutarch’s Table Talks”. Goteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis, 1989-1996., ad loc).
  • 34
    Brenk (1977BRENK, F. “In Mist Apparelled. Religious Themes in Plutarch’s Moralia and Lives'”. Leiden: Brill, 1977., p. 155) also shares this opinion.
  • 35
    There is a similar definition of sipappsvq in De Fato (570) that also includes providence. The problem is that this work is considered apocryphal. See further details in Froidefond (1987FROIDEFOND, C. “Plutarque et le Platonisme”. ANRW, II.36.1, pp. 184-233, 1987., p. 226).
  • 36
    It is worth noting that the verbs of his speech are either participles or forms of the third person.
  • 37
    Plutarch himself noticed the Stoic tendency to merge εἱµαρµένη and πρόνοια in De Stoic. rep. 1050A-B (= SVF II. 937).
  • 38
    On this subject vide Opsomer (2014OPSOMER, J. "Plutarch and the Stoics". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch. Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 88-103., pp. 91-93).
  • 39
    I chose to write ‘God’ with a capital ‘G’ because Plutarch’s religious doctrine is substantially monotheistic. Even if he assumes the existence of many divine entities, he recognizes the existence of a supreme God. On this subject vide Hirsch-Luipold (2014HIRSCH-LUIPOLD, R. "Religion and Myth". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch. Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 163-176., pp. 166-170), who suggests the label ‘polylatric monotheism’ for Plutarch’s views on religion.
  • 40
    This vocabular link is also in the De E (e.g. 373A5-6, 382F5-383A4). However, this does not entail that Plutarch considered Ideas as “the thoughts of God”; see further discussion in Ferrari (1995_____. “Dio, Idee e Materia. La Struttura del Cosmo in Plutarco di Cheronea.” Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1995., pp. 242-247); Froidefond (1987FROIDEFOND, C. “Plutarque et le Platonisme”. ANRW, II.36.1, pp. 184-233, 1987., pp. 225-227).
  • 41
    This polemical interpretation is rejected by Proclus (in Tim. 1.319.15-16). For a thorough analysis of this ζήτηµα, see Ferrari (1996_____. “Dio: Padre e Artefice. La Teologia di Plutarco in Plat. Quaest. 2”. In: GALLO, I. Plutarco e la Religione. Atti del VI Convegno Plutarcheo (Ravello, 29-31 maggio 1995). Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1996. pp. 395-409., pp. 395-409).
  • 42
    This authorial problem is raised by Diogenianus in the first lines of the πρόβληµα.
  • 43
    See Grg. 508a; Lg. 757b-c; R. 558c.
  • 44
    Cf. Pl. Ti. 53c-56b.
  • 45
    On Plutarch’s use of the platonic doctrine of the mathematical rationalization of the cosmos see Ferrari (1995_____. “Dio, Idee e Materia. La Struttura del Cosmo in Plutarco di Cheronea.” Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1995., pp. 117-147).
  • 46
    Plutarch refers this conception of God in the De Iside 373A, 377E-F, 382F-383A. See further in Hershbell (1992FROIDEFOND, C. “Plutarque et le Platonisme”. ANRW, II.36.1, pp. 184-233, 1987., p. 3348); Karamanolis (2006KARAMANOLIS, G. “Plato and Aristotle in Agreement? Platonists on Aristotle from Antiochus to Porphyry.” Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006., p. 109); Babut (1969BABUT, D. “Plutarque et le Stoïcisme”. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1969., pp. 453-465); Cacciatore (2009CACCIATORE, P. “È il Dio degli Stoici Filantropo?”. In: FERREIRA, J. et al. (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 289-295., p. 290).
  • 47
    Vide Dillon (1996DILLON, J. “The Middle Platonists. 80 B.C to A.D. 220”. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996., pp. 192-193). For a thorough analysis on Plutarch’s ὁµοίωσις τῷ θεῷ, see Becchi (1996)BECCHI, F. “Plutarco e la Dottrina dell’GMOIQLIL TQ ©EQI tra Platonismo e Aristotelismo”. In GALLO. I. Plutarco e la Religions. Atti del VI Convegno Plutarcheo (Ravello, 29-31 maggio 1995). Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1996. pp. 321-335..
  • 48
    See further details in Ferrari (1995_____. “Dio, Idee e Materia. La Struttura del Cosmo in Plutarco di Cheronea.” Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1995., pp. 156-158; 2009, p. 90).
  • 49
    For Greek authors, I followed the Liddell & Scott's Greek-English Lexicon abbreviations. For Latin authors, I followed the Glare's Oxford Latin Dictionary abbreviations.

References

  • ARRIGHETTI, G. “Epicuro: Opere”. Torino: Einaudi, 1960.
  • BABUT, D. “Plutarque et le Stoïcisme”. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1969.
  • _____. "Plutarque, Aristote, et l’ Aristotélisme". In: VAN DER STOCKT, L. (ed.). Plutarchea Lovaniensia: a Miscellany of Essays on Plutarch Louvain: Université Catholique de Louvain, 1996. pp. 1-28.
  • BAILEY, C. “Epicurus: the Extant Remains”. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1926.
  • BECCHI, F. “Plutarco e la Dottrina dell’GMOIQLIL TQ ©EQI tra Platonismo e Aristotelismo”. In GALLO. I. Plutarco e la Religions. Atti del VI Convegno Plutarcheo (Ravello, 29-31 maggio 1995) Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1996. pp. 321-335.
  • _____. "Plutarch, Aristotle, and the Peripatetics". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 73-87.
  • BOULOGNE, J. “Plutarque et l’épicurisme”. Paris: Doctorat soutenue à Paris 4, 1986.
  • BOWIE, E. "Greek Table-talk before Plato". Rhetorica, 11, pp. 355-71, 1993.
  • BRENK, F. “In Mist Apparelled. Religious Themes in Plutarch’s Moralia and Lives'” Leiden: Brill, 1977.
  • _____. "'In Learned Conversation'. Plutarch’s Symposiac Literature and the Elusive Authorial Voice". In: FERREIRA, J. et al (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 51-62.
  • BROADIE, S. “Aristotle and Beyond. Essays on Metaphysics and Ethics”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
  • CACCIATORE, P. “È il Dio degli Stoici Filantropo?”. In: FERREIRA, J. et al (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 289-295.
  • DIELS, H. & KRANZ, W. “Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker”. 3 Vols. 6th ed. repr. 2005. Zürich: Weidmann, 1952.
  • DIHLE, A. “The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity”. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982.
  • DILLON, J. “The Middle Platonists. 80 B.C to A.D. 220”. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996.
  • _____. "Plutarch and Platonism". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 61-72.
  • FERRARI, F. “Simposio e Filosofia: il Problema del «Dio Geometra»”. In: FERREIRA, J. et al (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 87-96.
  • _____. “Dio: Padre e Artefice. La Teologia di Plutarco in Plat. Quaest. 2”. In: GALLO, I. Plutarco e la Religione. Atti del VI Convegno Plutarcheo (Ravello, 29-31 maggio 1995) Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1996. pp. 395-409.
  • _____. “Dio, Idee e Materia. La Struttura del Cosmo in Plutarco di Cheronea.” Napoli: M. D'Auria, 1995.
  • FERREIRA, J. et al (eds.). “Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch”. Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009.
  • FREDE, M. “A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought”. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011.
  • FROIDEFOND, C. “Plutarque et le Platonisme”. ANRW, II.36.1, pp. 184-233, 1987.
  • HEINZE, R. “Xenocrates”. Stuttgart: Teubner, 1892.
  • HERSHBELL, J. “Plutarch and Stoicism”. ANRW, II.36, pp. 3336-3352, 1992.
  • HIRSCH-LUIPOLD, R. "Religion and Myth". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 163-176.
  • HOBDEN, F. “The Symposion in Ancient Greek Society and Thought”. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013.
  • JOHNSON, M. “Aristotle on Teleology”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
  • JONES, R. “The Platonism of Plutarch”. Menasha: George Banta Publishing Company, 1916.
  • KARAMANOLIS, G. “Plato and Aristotle in Agreement? Platonists on Aristotle from Antiochus to Porphyry.” Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
  • KECHAGIA, E. "Philosophy in Plutarch’s Table Talk. In Jest or in Earnest?". In: KLOTZ, F., OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. (eds.). The Philosopher S Banquet. Plutarch S Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. pp. 77-104.
  • KECHAGIA-OVSEIKO, E. (2011). "Plutarch and Epicureanism". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 104-120.
  • KLOTZ, F. “Portraits of the Philosopher: Plutarch’s Self-Presentation in the Quaestiones convivales” CQ, 57.2, pp. 650-667, 2007.
  • KLOTZ, F., OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. (eds.). “The Philosopher’s Banquet. Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
  • LAKS, A., MOST, G. “Early Greek Philosophy”. Cambridge Mass./London: Harvard University Press, 9 Vols., 2016.
  • LONG, A., SEDLEY, D. “The Hellenistic Philosophers”. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 2 Vols., 1987.
  • LOPES, R. “The Omnipresence of Philosophy in Plutarch’s Quaestiones Convivales" In: FERREIRA, J. et al (eds.). Symposion and Philanthropia in Plutarch Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2009. pp. 415-424.
  • MARTÍN GARCÍA, F. “Plutarco. Obras Morales y de Costumbres (Moralia) IV (Charlas de Sobremesa)”. Madrid: Gredos, 1987.
  • MONTIEL, J. "Superstición y ateísmo en la crítica antiepicúrea de Plutarco". In: LEÃO, D., FRAZIER, F. (eds.). Tychè et Pronoia - La marche du monde selon Plutarque Coimbra: Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra, 2010. pp. 57-68.
  • MOSSMAN, J. “Plutarch’s Dinner of the Seven Wise Men and its place in symposion literature”. In: MOSSMAN, J. (ed.). Plutarch and his Intellectual World London: Duckworth, 1997. pp. 119-140.
  • MURRAY, O. “Sympotica. A Symposium on the Symposion”. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.
  • OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. "Peripatetic Knowledge in Plutarch’s Table Talk" In: KLOTZ, F., OIKONOMOPOULOU, K. (eds.). The Philosopher’s Banquet. Plutarch’s Table Talk in the Intellectual Culture of the Roman Empire Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. pp. 105-130.
  • OPSOMER, J. "Plutarch and the Stoics". In: BECK, M. (ed.). A Companion to Plutarch Malden/Oxford/Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. pp. 88-103.
  • ORFANOS, C., CARRIÈRE, J. “Symposium: banquet et représentations en Grèce et à Rome”. Toulouse: Université de Toulouse, 2003.
  • ROMERI, L. “Philosophes entre Mots et Mets. Plutarque, Lucien et Athénée autour de la Table de Platon”. Grenoble: Jérôme Millón, 2002.
  • SEDLEY, D. "Platonic Causes". Phronesis, XLIII/2, pp. 114-132, 1998.
  • TAYLOR, C. “Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics”. Books II-IV Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
  • TEODORSSON, S.-T. “A Commentary on Plutarch’s Table Talks”. Goteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis, 1989-1996.
  • TORRACA, L. “I Presupositi della Tyche Plutarchea”. In: GALLO, I. (ed.). Plutarco e la Religione. Atti del VI Convegno Plutarcheo (Ravello, 29-31 maggio 1995) Napoli: M. DAuria, 1996. pp. 105-155.
  • USENER, H. Epicúrea Lipsiae: [s.e.], 1887.
  • VAN DER STOCKT, L. “Aspects of the Ethics and poetics of the Dialogue in the Corpus Plularcheum" In: GALLO, I., MORESCHINI, C. (eds.). I Generi Letterari in Plutarco. Atti del VIII Convegno Plutarcheo, Pisa, 2-4 giugno 1999 Napoli: M. D'Aura 2000. PP. 93-50.
  • VETTA, M. “Plutarco e il ‘Genere Simposio’”. In: GALLO, I., MORESCHINI, C. (eds.). I Generi Letterari in Plutarco. Atti del VIII Convegno Plutarcheo, Pisa, 2-4 giugno 1999 Napoli: M. D'Auria, 2000. pp. 217-229.
  • VON ARNIM, H. “Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta”. Stutgardia: Bibliotheca Teubneriana, 1903-1905.
  • XENOPHONTOS, S. “Ethical Education in Plutarch. Moralising Agents and Contexts”. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter, 2016.

Publication Dates

  • Publication in this collection
    10 Feb 2021
  • Date of issue
    Sep-Dec 2020

History

  • Received
    13 Sept 2019
  • Accepted
    29 Oct 2019
Faculdade de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas da UFMG Av. Antônio Carlos, 6627 Campus Pampulha, CEP: 31270-301 Belo Horizonte MG - Brasil, Tel: (31) 3409-5025, Fax: (31) 3409-5041 - Belo Horizonte - MG - Brazil
E-mail: kriterion@fafich.ufmg.br